Follesdal, Andreas: Add international courts to The Idea of Human Rights and stir … on Beitz’ The Idea of Human Rights after 10 years. In: Álvarez, David; Rosas, João Cardoso (Ed.): The Idea of Human Rights Revisited: Charles Beitz and the Political Turn in the Philosophy of Human Rights, Routledge, 2023. (Type: Book Chapter | Abstract | Links | Tags: Human Rights, International courts, Publications)@inbook{RN52229, These reflections elaborates the theory of The Idea of Human Rights by addressing a topic that theory attempts to bracket: international and regional judicialization in the form of international courts and tribunals. Using the method of reflective equilibrium, the article argues that this exclusion is inconsistent. Including these international courts and tribunals (‘ICs’) prompts several changes to the original theory, and opens new research questions. The original theory is on the one hand too narrow regarding both the objectives and tools of international mechanisms of corrective concern. The account should consider further subsidiary modes of support. On the other hand the theory is too broad, in that it gives insufficient guidance to the judges of ICs and others able to effect changes. This leaves the theory incomplete, and open to similar criticism as the book raised against others. Accounts of the theory presented in The Idea of Human Rights,and of ICs and their roles regarding human rights allow us to explore some implications of ICs for The Idea of Human Rights.We then consider how if at all The Idea of Human Rights can guide international judges. |
Follesdal, Andreas: In defense of deference: International human rights as standards of review. In: Journal of Social Philosophy, vol. 54, no. 4, pp. 526-547, 2023. (Type: Journal Article | Abstract | Links | Tags: European Consensus, European Court of Human Rights, Human Rights, Margin of Appreciation, Publications)@article{RN52180, Member states of the Council of Europe subject themselves to judicial human rights review by the European Court of Human Rights. That Court in turn defers sometimes to the judgments of domestic courts about compliance, granting them a margin of discretion, more so when it sees a European consensus. This complex practice can be justified based on arguments about comparative epistemic expertise, respect for democratic decision making, and the need to avoid undue judicial discretion – juristocracy. While this account supports the general practice, it points to certain weaknesses and areas of improvement: the rules to nominate and elect judges and members of the Registry of the Court, the doctrine of the margin of appreciation, and the rationales for a European consensus. |
Follesdal, Andreas: A just yet unequal European Union: A defense of moderate economic inequality. In: Review of Social Economy, vol. 81, no. 1, pp. 8-36, 2023. (Type: Journal Article | Abstract | Links | Tags: EU – European Union, Federalism, John Rawls, Publications)@article{RN52113, What does justice require concerning socio-economic distribution among citizens of the European Union? The EU should reduce cross-national economic inequalities among inhabitants of different member states, but full economic distributive equality or a European ‘Difference Principle,’ may not be required. Individuals’ claim to more political influence over matters controlled by their own state in the quasi-federal EU may permit some economic inequality. Section 1 orients this contribution relative to arguments for a European universal income. Section 2 provides relevant features of the EU. Section 3 considers contractualist arguments against certain forms of economic inequality, while section 4 identifies a further argument in favour of equal shares of benefits of social cooperation, based on an interpretation of ‘social primary goods’ consistent with Rawls’ theory. Section 5 argues that these reasons for economic distributive equality must be weighed against more political influence over matters controlled by the individual’s sub-unit. |
Follesdal, Andreas; Ruud, Morten; Kjeldgaard-Pedersen, Astrid: Situated and Universal: Special Issue in Honor of Geir Ulfstein. Nordic Journal of International Law, 2022. (Type: Book | Tags: Publications, Special issues)@book{RN52681, |
Follesdal, Andreas; Ruud, Morten; Kjeldgaard-Pedersen, Astrid: Introduction to Special Issue in Honor of Geir Ulfstein. In: Nordic Journal of International Law, vol. 91, no. 4, pp. 541-543, 2022. (Type: Journal Article | Links | Tags: )@article{RN55201, |
Follesdal, Andreas: The Significance of State Consent for the Legitimate Authority of Customary International Law. In: Merkouris, Panos; Kammerhofer, Jörg; Arajärvi, Noora (Ed.): The Theory, Practice and Interpretation of Customary International Law, pp. 105-136, Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, 2022. (Type: Book Chapter | Links | Tags: International law, Publications)@inbook{RN52115, |
Follesdal, Andreas: Federalism. In: Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy, no. 2022, 2022. (Type: Journal Article | Links | Tags: Federalism, Publications)@article{RN32630, |
Follesdal, Andreas: Add international courts to The Idea of Human Rights and stir … on Beitz’ The Idea of Human Rights after 10 years. In: Critical Review of International Social and Political Philosophy, vol. 25, no. 1, pp. 66-86, 2022. (Type: Journal Article | Abstract | Links | Tags: Human Rights, International courts, Publications)@article{RN51709, These reflections elaborates the theory of The Idea of Human Rights by addressing a topic that theory attempts to bracket: international and regional judicialization in the form of international courts and tribunals. Using the method of reflective equilibrium, the article argues that this exclusion is inconsistent. Including these international courts and tribunals (‘ICs’) prompts several changes to the original theory, and opens new research questions. The original theory is on the one hand too narrow regarding both the objectives and tools of international mechanisms of corrective concern. Reprinted 2023 in David Álvarez and João Cardoso Rosas (eds) The Idea of Human Rights Revisited: Charles Beitz and the Political Turn in the Philosophy of Human Rights, Routledge |
Hessler, Kristen; Follesdal, Andreas: Gender imbalance on the international bench: is normative legitimacy at stake?. In: Journal of Social Philosophy, vol. 52, no. 4, pp. 430-435, 2021. (Type: Journal Article | Abstract | Links | Tags: Gender, Human Rights, International courts, Publications)@article{RN52225, As norms of state sovereignty have evolved in an increasingly globalized world, international courts and tribunals have proliferated and expanded the scope of their authority. Some observers hail these developments as moral progress, representing the ascendancy of the rule of law rather than power politics in international relations. At the same time, the growing number of ICs, and their expanded scope and power, have triggered extensive critiques and political resistance against them. ..However, ICs have received increasing criticism regarding issues of representation among judges….Some recent developments on this issue are hopeful. ..However, a broader perspective reveals that these developments indicate only marginal progress. As of March, 2021 women constitute only 24% of sitting judges on international tribunals, 22% of judges on human rights tribunals, and only 13% of regional court judges…. |
Gebrewahd, Meressa Tsehaye; Rowe, Colin; Schutter, Helder; Follesdal, Andreas: Mediating unity and diversity through Federalism in Ethiopia. Special Issue. International Journal on Minority and Group Rights, 2021. (Type: Book | Links | Tags: Federalism, Publications, Special issues)@book{RN51662, |
Follesdal, Andreas; Ratner, Steven: Introducing David Lefkowitz’s Philosophy and International Law. In: EJIL:Talk – Blog of the European Journal of International Law, 2021. (Type: Journal Article | Links | Tags: )@article{RN52201, |
Follesdal, Andreas: Stability and trust in federations with ethnic territories and a secession clause – challenges and opportunities for Ethiopia. In: International Journal on Minority and Group Rights, 2021. (Type: Journal Article | Abstract | Links | Tags: Federalism, Publications)@article{RN51659, How might Ethiopia maintain its federal structure within present territorial borders? Most federal states experience ‘constitutional contestation’ navigating between complete centralization and secession. We should expect further such instability in Ethiopia especially due to two factors: regions and political parties follow ethnic line; and a secession clause in the Ethiopian Constitution. The article identifies some suggestions for how to increase stability and trust under such circumstances, drawn from tentative international comparisons among ethnic-based federal states. Among the particular concerns are the interests of oppressed minorities and ways to quell calls for secession. … |
Follesdal, Andreas: Pure Public Goods and Beyond: How Legitimate International Courts Can Help Secure Global Public Goods Worth Having. In: Zyberi, Gentian (Ed.): Protecting Community Interests through International Law, pp. 59-98, Intersentia, Cambridge, 2021. (Type: Book Chapter | Abstract | Links | Tags: Climate, International courts, Publications)@inbook{RN51888, A frequent legitimacy challenge against international law and international courts is that they are too weak to prevent ‘free riders’ among states to help secure ‘Global Public Goods (GPG), such as resolving the climate crisis. This description, diagnosis, and prescription for how international law and ICs can and should enable GPG is unfortunate. The assumptions are too narrow, and distract our attention from other valuable contributions made by ICs—in terms of GPGs and beyond—and from other important challenges that ICs face. The shallow focus stifles our assessment of when international law and ICs may be legitimate authorities in general, and in relation to GPGs in particular. In fact, ICs’ legitimacy does not depend on their ability to trigger sanctions against states; they serve several valuable functions for many objectives other than GPGs, including monitoring and providing information about other states’ actions and preferences… |
Follesdal, Andreas: International human rights courts and the (international) rule of law: Part of the solution, part of the problem, or both?. In: Global Constitutionalism, vol. 10, no. 1, pp. 118-138, 2021. (Type: Journal Article | Abstract | Links | Tags: European Court of Human Rights, Human Rights, International courts, Publications)@article{RN50110, The present article seeks to shed some light on the central relationships between international rule of law norms and international human rights courts, whilst identifying some of the central normative concerns. The aim is partly theoretical, to lay out aspects of how to ‘extend’ or ‘extrapolate’ normative standards such as the rule of law from the domestic setting to international law and organizations; and to explore some modes of interaction between rule of law standards and international courts. The article also draws together relevant empirical findings to shed light on how some of these courts actually work to challenge and bolster rule of law standards. Section 1 sketches one way to ‘transpose’ domestic rule of law norms to international law and institutions – in particular, international human rights courts (IHRCs). We then move to consider two relationships between such standards and IHRCs – in particular, the European Court of Human Rights (ECtHR). Section 2 considers whether IHRCs themselves live up to such standards, in particular as regard selection of judges to secure both independence and accountability. Do IHRCs promote the rule of law among states as judicial organs in multilevel structures, or are they instruments of domination by strong states? I also consider other forms of bias important for ICs, in particular professional bias of the judges. Section 3 explores whether and how IHRCs may promote the rule of law within states: how they may help reduce domination, without themselves becoming new sources of unchecked discretion. The answers hold at best for the ECtHR, but may vary among IHRCs and among the states over which they have jurisdiction. |
Follesdal, Andreas: How many women judges are enough on international courts?. In: Journal of Social Philosophy, vol. 52, no. 4, pp. 436-458, 2021. (Type: Journal Article | Abstract | Links | Tags: Gender, International courts, Publications)@article{RN51724, NOTE: There are errors in the published text, see below for errata. A legitimate international court need not secure numerical sex equality on the bench – complete parity. The article argues that a commitment that institutions should treat all with equal concern requires not only token representation of both prevalent sexes, or a ‘critical mass’ of 15 -25%, but a ‘parity zone’ of 40% of each. Arguments of compassion , epistemic competence; and expressions of status equality favour a high threshold of both the prevalent sexes, and further requirements to ensure a broad range of backgrounds and perspectives among the international judges . The aim is to explore what these arguments require regarding the proportion of men and women on the international bench. The strongest of these arguments withstand criticisms that they ‘essentialize’ gender, or assume that elitist female international judges can represent all other women, or lead to a slippery slope where ICs must also ‘mirror’ a myriad of characteristics of the affected populations and constituencies . The many reasons to lament various unjust forms and levels of inequalities counsel different, only partly overlapping objectives. The composition and workings of ICs must satisfy the norms of impartiality independence and procedural fairness, especially because the ICs are tasked to uphold these very norms. The arguments support a parity zone, and several of the arguments entail that more judges – regardless of their own sex and gender – should be ‘gender sensitive,’ and that there should be further requirements to ensure more diversity of perspectives among the international judges. But there are no strong arguments for complete equal proportions of men and women – ‘sex parity’ – on the international bench. – ERRATA: The sentence which reads “The majority of its judges were female— six of 11, and the first among international courts and tribunals (ICs) to secure sex parity— that is, numerical equality.:” should be replaced by “It was only the second international court or tribunal (IC) where the majority of its judges are female— six of 11, and the first among ICs to secure sex parity— that is, numerical equality.” Footnote 1 should be expanded, to read ” —for institutions that standardly have an odd number of members. Six women and five men, http://www.african court.org/en/index.php/news/press-releases/item/245-three-new-judges-elected-to-the-african-court-on-human -and-peoples-rights-vp-justice-ben-kioko-re-elected-for-second-term <http://court.org/en/index.php/news/press-releases/item/245-three-new-judges-elected-to-the-african-court-on-human-and-peoples-rights-vp-justice-ben-kioko-re-elected-for-second-term> . While this court is the first to secure parity, it is the second to have a majority of women: in 2010, the International Criminal Court in 2010 included a majority of 11 women (out of 18 judges) (Chappell 2010). In 2021, the ICC has equal representation of male and female judges (https://www.icc-cpi.int/Publications/JudgesENG.pdf)”
|
Ulfstein, Geir; Ruud, Morten; Follesdal, Andreas: The Relationship Between the European Convention on Human Rights and Wider International Law – Special Issue. International Journal on Human Rights, 2020. (Type: Book | Abstract | Links | Tags: Human Rights, Publications, Special issues)@book{RN51661, Based on presentations at a seminar in Strasbourg 29-30 March 2017, to launch the work of the Drafting Group II of the Committee of experts on the system of the Convention (DH-SYSC-II) of the Council of Europe. The seminar was organized in cooperation between the PluriCourts Centre on the Legitimacy of the International Judiciary, at the University of Oslo, and the Council of Europe. |
Ulfstein, Geir; Ruud, Morten; Follesdal, Andreas: The European Convention on Human Rights and other parts of international law. In: International Journal on Human Rights, vol. 24, no. 7, pp. 913-16, 2020. (Type: Journal Article | Abstract | Links | Tags: European Court of Human Rights, Human Rights)@article{RN51660, The relationship between the European Convention on Human Rights (ECHR) and other parts of international law has been the subject of increasing debate, following several recent judgments by the European Court of Human Rights (ECtHR). Indeed, the Council of Europe Steering Committee for Human Rights (CDDH) report on The Longer-term Future of the System of the European Convention on Human Rights of 11 December 2015 identified the ‘place of the of the Convention mechanisms in the European and international legal order” as one of the four areas to be decisive for the effectiveness and viability of the Convention system. |
Follesdal, Andreas: Survey Article: The Legitimacy of International Courts. In: Journal of Political Philosophy, vol. 28, no. 4, pp. 475-499, 2020. (Type: Journal Article | Abstract | Links | Tags: International courts, Publications)@article{RN51506, States are free, yet everywhere live under international courts and tribunals (ICs). As they proliferate and gain power across ever more domains, ICs become targets of resistance and criticism that they are illegitimate authorities. What reasons might a state have to defer to an IC’s judgment or interpretation, even when the state regards it as mistaken, and even when it conflicts with the interests and objectives of government? Section I sketches the multiple tasks of ICs, in complex interdependence with other actors. Their core task is to adjudicate disputes through interpretation and application of international law by legal methods. This may also contribute indirectly to a range of further tasks. Section II addresses some aspects of the relation between normative legitimacy of ICs and descriptive legitimacy – actors’ beliefs therein. Section III shows how a wide range of legitimacy challenges concern ways ICs fail to carry out their tasks. This account does not seek to provide substantive arguments or seek to show that all such criticisms are correct. The aims are rather to make many such criticisms comprehensible as legitimacy concerns, to provide a rationale for popular taxonomies of legitimacy criticisms, and to indicate which premises and arguments are required for such criticisms to be sound. |
Follesdal, Andreas: Religion and the State – the European Court of Human Rights and the ‘Lautsi’ case of the European Court of Human Rights about crucifixes in Italian class rooms. In: Ehlers, Dirk; Glaser, Henning (Ed.): State and Religion: Between Conflict and Cooperation, pp. 315 – 330, Nomos, Baden Baden, 2020. (Type: Book Chapter | Abstract | Links | Tags: European Court of Human Rights, Human Rights, Margin of Appreciation)@inbook{RN49938, The relationship between political authorities and religious communities is complex and controversial. One area where the tensions are evident is in public education. Tensions arise when the state seeks to include or exclude contested religious symbols and teachings within the public educational system.The European Court of Human Rights’ track record may seem inconsistent. It has restricted religious teaching in textbooks allowed Turkey to prohibit students from wearing religious headscarves at university , allowed Switzerland to prohibit primary school teachers from wearing headscarves , and allows Italy to require crucifixes on school walls – after first denying Italy that authority. There are several ways to try to make some sense of this cluster of decisions. The explanation which will be addressed here is the ECtHR’s practice to grant states a ‘Margin of Appreciation’ (MA). This article seeks to bring a more precise MA doctrine to bear on the Lautsi case concerning crucifixes on school walls, to assess whether the ECtHR decision and doctrine withstands criticism that it is too vague, or that it is poorly applied in this particular case. The first section presents the Lautsi case, the following sections attend to various elements of the MA doctrine of the court. We return at the end to consider whether critics of the MA doctrine are right. |
Follesdal, Andreas: Challenges to the legitimacy of the European Union: When and how are European courts also part of the solution?. In: xx, 2019. (Type: Journal Article | Abstract | Tags: Federalism)@article{RN51449, The legitimacy deficits of the European Union has long been a rallying cry for ‘Eurosceptics’ of various kinds. Section I considers how we are to think about the ‘legitimacy challenges’ of the EU, by bringing to bear Joseph Raz’ service conception. This approach explores ways to reconceptualize and rethink the notion of legitimacy in the EU, characterized as a multilevel legal order whose task is to serve its citizens and others on this globe. This frame may help move the discussion forward, identify more precisely some of the current weaknesses of the EU and what might alleviate them. Section II uses this account to identify some of the legitimacy challenges of the EU, several due to its federal elements. The EU is trusted to promote multiple objectives within various constraints. The federal features of the EU has implications for the appropriate substantive standards of economic solidarity and ‘social cohesion’ across states and regions. The possibilities of secession affects the bargains about tasks, burden sharing, and the willingness to pay some short term costs for the sake of longer term benefits – precisely some of the task political authority is often set up to help resolve. And the EU is an asymmetric legal order: consider the Eurozone, Schengen-Europe, and so forth. One implication is that different states and citizens will correctly hold different views about the appropriate task of the shared institutions, reflecting deep and correct disagreement about what the federation is for. Section III considers how the European courts may alleviate some but not all these challenges. |
Follesdal, Andreas: Legitimacy criticisms of international courts: Not only Fuzzy Rhetoric?. In: Sadurski, Wojciech; Sevel, Michael; Walton, Kevin (Ed.): Legitimacy: The State and Beyond, pp. 223-237, Oxford University Press, Oxford, 2019. (Type: Book Chapter | Abstract | Links | Tags: Human Rights, International courts, Publications)@inbook{RN50854, Many claims that international courts (ICs) are illegitimate are related in complex ways – differently in fields ranging from human rights to trade. This is not to deny that some talk of the illegitimacy of ICs is inaccurate or wrong. But it is possible and indeed valuable to develop a coherent account that connects several various usages, so as to specify better, worse and downright mistaken claims concerning the legitimacy of ICs. normative legitimacy provides helpful unity to many of the canvassed forms of legitimacy. The particular substantive normative conception of global justice to be respected and promoted by these institutions is not central to this task. I develop the outline of a theory by drawing on Joseph Raz’ ‘service conception’ of normatively legitimate authority, David Easton’s ‘systems analysis,’ and a cosmopolitan normative theory. Section 1 sketches relevant aspects of Raz’ account of legitimate authority: the service conception. Section 2 lays out some normative standards relevant for the ICs. The next sections then elaborate why, on the service conception, various legitimacy conceptions matter for normative legitimacy: why legality matters (section 3) including some reasons for the (limited) significance of state consent – even by rogue states. Section 4 starts to explore why and when actual compliance is important but not always decisive. Section 5 considers why the performance or effects of an IC matters. |
Follesdal, Andreas: The European Research Council @ 10: Whither hopes and fears?. In: European Political Science, vol. 18, no. 2, pp. 237-247, 2019. (Type: Journal Article | Abstract | Links | Tags: ERC – European Research Council, Publications, Research policy)@article{RN50945, While ten years is too early to draw broad conclusions, the European Research Council does seem to have succeeded in promoting excellent and basic research in Europe, both through its own projects and by affecting standards and aspirations more broadly. It has affected widely shared conceptions of scholarly excellence and introduced new measures of academic esteem with more attention to rigorous peer review – also in the social sciences and the humanities. One concern is that the portability of grants may have fueled the clustering of research talent and reputation toward some institutions and some states, away from others. The benefits of the ERC in promoting research quality across Europe in the longer term may be at risk unless some parties take steps to correct the imbalance. |
Follesdal, Andreas: The European Research Council @ 10: What has it done to us?. In: European Political Science, vol. 18, no. 2, pp. 234-36, 2019. (Type: Journal Article | Links | Tags: ERC – European Research Council, Publications, Research policy)@article{RN50944, |
Follesdal, Andreas: A better Signpost, not a better walking Stick: How to evaluate the European Consensus doctrine. In: Kapotas, Panos; Tzevelokos, Vassilis (Ed.): Building Consensus on European Consensus: Judicial Interpretation of Human Rights in Europe and Beyond, pp. 189-209, Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, 2019. (Type: Book Chapter | Abstract | Links | Tags: European Consensus, European Court of Human Rights, Human Rights, Margin of Appreciation)@inbook{RN50770, One of the more contested interpretative practices of the European Court of Human Rights (ECtHR) is its sighting of an ‘emerging European consensus’ (EuC) and the implications that the Court draws. If this practice is to be kept, suggestions for its improvement should be guided by the normatively justifiable roles such a practice should play, be it as part of the Court’s ‘dynamic interpretation’ of the Convention, or as a means to specify the margin of appreciation doctrine, or both. This requires closer reflection about which are sound reasons for the Court to appeal to EuC. Section 9.1 sketches the current practice of the Court. Section 9.2 explains why several critics claim that the EuC practice is too vague and otherwise problematic. Section 9.3 considers some of the most prominent arguments in favour of EuC, noting that several of these arguments fail to consider the peculiar subsidiary role of the human rights review by the ECtHR within the multi-level European legal order. |
Squatrito, Theresa; Young, Oran; Follesdal, Andreas; Ulfstein, Geir: The Performance of International Courts and Tribunals. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, 2018, ((i) the IC’s output: its judgments and interpretations; (ii) its outcome in the sense of states’ compliance with particular judgments; and (iii) the ultimate broader impact of such compliance on the ground.). (Type: Book | Abstract | Links | Tags: Edited books, Human Rights, International courts, Publications)@book{RN50115, International courts and tribunals now operate globally and in several world regions, playing significant roles in international law and global governance. However, these courts vary significantly in terms of their practices, procedures, and the outcomes they produce. Why do some international courts perform better than others? Which factors affect the outcome of these courts and tribunals? The Performance of International Courts and Tribunals is an interdisciplinary study featuring approaches, methods and authorship from law and political science, which proposes the concept of performance to describe the processes and outcomes of international courts. It develops a framework for evaluating and explaining performance by offering a broad comparative analysis of international courts, covering several world regions and the areas of trade, investment, the environment, human rights and criminal law, and offers interdisciplinary accounts to explain how and why international court performance varies. |
Squatrito, Theresa; Young, Oran; Follesdal, Andreas; Ulfstein, Geir: A framework for evaluating the performance of international courts and tribunals. In: Squatrito, Theresa; Young, Oran; Follesdal, Andreas; Ulfstein, Geir (Ed.): The Performance of International Courts and Tribunals, pp. 3-35, Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, 2018. (Type: Book Chapter | Abstract | Links | Tags: International courts, Publications)@inbook{RN50987, While prior studies have tended to focus on specific questions relating either to the design or to the effects of international courts, we develop an integrated framework for the study of the performance of ICs. .. We explore factors that may explain the patterns of performance we observe. …We are interested both in the outcomes courts produce and the processes through which they arrive at judgments…. To know whether regimes or governance systems are effective, then, we argue that it is imperative to ask whether international courts perform their roles well or poorly. |
Ryssevik, Jostein; Føllesdal, Andreas; Thorsen, Dag Einar; Aubert, Axel: Politikk og menneskerettigheter. Aschehoug, Oslo, 2018. (Type: Book | Links | Tags: Human Rights)@book{RN51004, |
Grossman, Nienke; Cohen, Harlan; Follesdal, Andreas; Ulfstein, Geir: The legitimacy of international courts. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, 2018. (Type: Book | Links | Tags: Edited books, International courts, Publications)@book{RN50121, |
Grossman, Nienke; Cohen, Harlan; Follesdal, Andreas; Ulfstein, Geir: Legitimacy and international courts – a framework. In: Grossman, Nienke; Cohen, Harlan; Follesdal, Andreas; Ulfstein, Geir (Ed.): The legitimacy of international courts, pp. 1-40, Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, 2018. (Type: Book Chapter | Abstract | Links | Tags: International courts, Publications)@inbook{RN50929, This Introduction surveys some of the key contributions of this volume and distills some of the lessons of its varied chapters for the legitimacy of international courts. Parts II and III are largely conceptual in approach, exploring what legitimacy means for each and all of the courts. Part II explores the concept of legitimacy as it pertains to international courts, examining the relationship between source, process, and results-oriented aspects of IC legitimacy and the relationship between legitimacy, justice, democracy, and effectiveness. Part III looks more closely at the chapters in this volume and explores their contributions to the discussions above, as well as their lessons regarding the relationship between sociological and normative legitimacy. Part IV takes a more functional approach, exploring how various factors internal or external to particular courts have contributed to those courts’ normative or sociological legitimacy. It considers international courts in their context, examining the relationship between the specific goals, design choices, audiences, institutional contexts and IC legitimacy. It explores three models of how these factors interact in this volume’s chapters to either support of undermine an international court’s sociological or normative legitimacy. Part V provides thumbnail summaries of each the chapters that follow. |
Follesdal, Andreas; Ulfstein, Geir: The Judicialization of International Law – A Mixed Blessing?. Oxford University Press, Oxford, 2018. (Type: Book | Abstract | Links | Tags: Edited books, International courts, Publications)@book{RN50775, The influence of international courts is ubiquitous, covering areas from the law of the sea to international criminal law. This judicialization of international law is often lauded for bringing effective global governance, upholding the rule of law, and protecting the right of individuals. Yet at what point does the omnipresence of the international judiciary shackle national sovereign freedom? And can the lack of political accountability be justified? Follesdal and Ulfstein bring together the crème de la crème of the legal academic world to ask the big questions for the international judiciary: whether they are there for mere dispute settlement or to set precedent, and how far they can enforce international obligations without impacting on democratic self-determination. |
Follesdal, Andreas; Ulfstein, Geir: International Courts and Tribunals: Rise and Reactions. In: Follesdal, Andreas; Ulfstein, Geir (Ed.): The Judicialization of International Law – A Mixed Blessing?, pp. 1-8, Oxford University Press, Oxford, 2018. (Type: Book Chapter | Abstract | Links | Tags: International courts, Publications)@inbook{RN50780, International courts and tribunals (ICs) are increasing in number and importance. They address an expanding variety of issues, ranging from the law of the sea to international criminal law. .. international relations are increasingly judicialized. The present book maps and assesses this development – and reactions thereto, because the trends have met with mixed responses… |
Follesdal, Andreas: Power or Authority; Actions or Beliefs. In: Alter, Karen; Helfer, Laurence; Madsen, Mikael Rask (Ed.): International Court Authority, pp. 412-421, Oxford University Press, New York, 2018. (Type: Book Chapter | Abstract | Links | Tags: International courts, Publications)@inbook{RN50401, Institutional, political and social circumstances affect the impact of international courts (‘ICs’). The valuable and intellectually intriguing aim of the project in this volume, ‘The Variable Authority of International Courts’ is to develop and apply a metric to assess the effects of some of these contexts. The chapter discusses two questions concerning the project. What do they seek to measure with their metric – and are the findings actually about authority? Furthermore, AHM go to great lengths to proclaim methodological agnosticism about actors’ beliefs and motives, and argue for the irrelevance of normative legitimacy for this research project. Yet the former claim seems incorrect and the second is both unnecessary and ill defended. |
Follesdal, Andreas: More than meets the eye – and less: On The Internationalists. In: Global Constitutionalism, vol. 7, no. 3, pp. 330-341, 2018. (Type: Journal Article | Abstract | Links | Tags: International courts, Publications)@article{RN51105, Review of O Hathaway and S Shapiro The Internationalists (2017). These comments explore further some game theoretical themes, of how outlawing of war led to profound changes in international relations even when the norm was breached. The Peace Pact arguably contributed to avoid war by creating institutions – such as international courts – that helped stabilize an assurance game among states by providing trustworthy information and commitments, in turn influencing practices and beliefs concerning mutual non-aggression. Second, the authors at times claim that the Peace Pact was not only a cause of, but the cause of the massive shift in reduced warfare. Further arguments would be required to substantiate that this treaty not only was a necessary condition, but the trigger that ‘began a cascade’ (xv). Other factors might also have been necessary, and equally deserving of the label ‘triggers,’ – such as increased global interdependence, or democratization. The authors might best modify their claim. Third, the authors claim not only to present a historical account, but also to draw lessons for the future. At a time when international norms and institutions are under severe pressure, such lessons are very welcome. However, there are reasons to be less optimistic than the authors about the extent of lessons we can draw from The Internationalists about how to preserve and improve on the New World Order of the Pact, rather than backsliding into the Old World Order. |
Follesdal, Andreas: The Legitimate Authority of International Courts and its Limits: A challenge to Raz’ Service Conception?. In: Capps, Patrick; Olsen, Henrik Palmer (Ed.): Legal authority beyond the state, pp. 188-205, Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, 2018. (Type: Book Chapter | Abstract | Links | Tags: International courts, Publications)@inbook{RN50652, Very public challenges to international courts (ICs) by state governments, legislatures, domestic or international courts, corporations, investors or civil society groups are often draped in terms of ‘legitimacy’. The challenges provoke several questions. Why should such ‘compliance constituencies’ defer to ICs’ judgments at all? More precisely: when do ICs’ judgments give such constituencies reason to act differently than they would otherwise – and when do they not? The present contribution argues that states’ disobedience may be justified due to the substantive contents of the particular ruling by an IC. Section 1 provides a brief sketch of Raz’s ‘Service account’ of legitimacy, and addresses some criticisms relevant to our concerns. Section 2 brings this account to bear on ICs, and lays out some of its distinguishing features by comparing it to the influential accounts of Daniel Bodansky and Yuval Shany. Section 3 turns to consider how this account accommodates and even justifies cases of disobedience against ICs. |
Follesdal, Andreas: Constitutionalization, not democratization: how to assess the legitimacy of international courts. In: Grossman, Nienke; Cohen, Harlan; Follesdal, Andreas; Ulfstein, Geir (Ed.): The legitimacy of international courts, pp. 307-337, Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, 2018. (Type: Book Chapter | Abstract | Links | Tags: International courts, Publications)@inbook{RN50335, Several authors – including Armin von Bogdandy and Ingo Venzke, Allan Buchanan and Robert Keohane, Gráinne De Búrca, and Nienke Grossman address the legitimacy deficits of international courts (ICs). They propose the ‘democratization’ of ICs, by which they often mean to increase their transparency, accountability or participation by various parties. There are other, better reasons to value transparency, accountability and participation concerning ICs than as building blocks of democracy, namely insofar as they contribute to valuable forms of constitutionalization of the global basic structure. Moreover, they can be valuable even when such changes do not advance democracy of the kind worth having. We should not assume that democracy is the touchstone for all legitimate modes of governance. TWe should distinguish between democratic institutions of decision-making, the normative principles that justify such institutions, and important features of such institutions that contribute to their justification, such as accountability, participation and transparency. It is only calls for the first of these – formalized institutions of decision-making – which should be considered democratication proper. |
Follesdal, Andreas: Appreciating the Margin of Appreciation. In: Etinson, Adam (Ed.): Human Rights: Moral or Political?, pp. 269-294, Oxford University Press, Oxford, 2018. (Type: Book Chapter | Abstract | Links | Tags: Democratic theory, European Court of Human Rights, Human Rights, Margin of Appreciation, Publications)@inbook{RN49344, How should an international human rights court best pay due respect to both the treaty and to its sovereign creators? The European Court of Human Rights (ECtHR) is a prime case. It reviews whether states uphold their obligations under the European Convention on Human Rights (ECHR). The Court is also authorized to rule on whether states may violate certain of their citizens’ rights – as the Convention permits – in order to protect morals, the conflicting rights of others, national security or other considerations (e.g. Articles 8 and 15). One mechanism that arguably serves to reduce the risk that the ECtHR will abuse its power is the margin of appreciation (MA) doctrine that the Court has developed. The Court grants states the authority to decide, in some cases, whether they are in compliance with their treaty obligations. Is the MA doctrine a sound response to this perceived dilemma between majoritarian democracy and protection of human rights? The present chapter presents and defends some form of the MA doctrine precisely as a contribution by the Court to both protect human rights and to promote domestic democracies. I shall also suggest reforms to render it more legitimate. |
Føllesdal, Andreas: Humanistisk forskning for et samfunn i forandring. In: Nytt Norsk Tidsskrift, vol. 34, no. 1, pp. 51-57, 2017, ISSN: 0800-336x. (Type: Journal Article | Abstract | Links | Tags: Research policy)@article{RN51794, Dagens forskningspolitikk er ikke tilpasset humanioras særegne utfordringer. Hvis myndighetene ønsker å opprettholde humanioras samfunnsoppdrag, må rammevilkårene også håndtere disse utfordringene…. |
Saul, Matthew; Follesdal, Andreas; Ulfstein, Geir: The International Human Rights Judiciary and National Parliaments: Europe and Beyond. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, 2017. (Type: Book | Abstract | Links | Tags: Edited books, European Court of Human Rights, Human Rights)@book{RN52622, The emerging international human rights judiciary (IHRJ) threatens national democratic processes and ‘hollows out’ the scope of domestic and democratic decision-making, some argue. This new analysis confronts this head on by examining the interplay between national parliaments and the IHRJ, proposing that it advances parliament’s efforts. Taking Europe and the European Court of Human Rights as its focus – drawing on theory, doctrine and practice – the authors answer a series of key questions. What role should parliaments play in realising human rights? Which factors influence the effects of the IHRJ on national parliaments’ efforts? How can the IHRJ adjust its influence on parliamentary process? And what triggers the backlash against the IHRJ from parliaments and when? Here, the authors lay foundations for better informed scholarship and legal practice in the future, as well as a better understanding of how to improve the effectiveness and validity of the IHRJ. |
Føllesdal, Andreas; Ruud, Morten; Ulfstein, Geir: Menneskerettighetene og Norge: Rettsutvikling, rettsliggjøring og demokrati. Universitetsforlaget, Oslo, 2017. (Type: Book | Tags: Edited books)@book{RN51030, |
Føllesdal, Andreas; Ruud, Morten; Ulfstein, Geir: De internasjonale menneskerettighetene og Norge: Spenninger og samspill. In: Føllesdal, Andreas; Ruud, Morten; Ulfstein, Geir (Ed.): Menneskerettighetene og Norge: Rettsutvikling, rettsliggjøring og demokrati, pp. 13-32, Universitetsforlaget, Oslo, 2017. (Type: Book Chapter | Tags: Human Rights)@inbook{RN51031, |
Follesdal, Andreas: Tracking justice democratically. In: Social Epistemology, vol. 31, no. 3, pp. 324-339, 2017. (Type: Journal Article | Abstract | Links | Tags: Democratic theory, European Court of Human Rights, Human Rights, Publications)@article{RN50172, Is international judicial human rights review anti-democratic and therefore illegitimate, and objectionably epistocratic to boot? Or is such review compatible with – and even a recommended component of – an epistemic account of democracy? This article defends the latter position, laying out the case for the legitimacy, possibly democratic legitimacy of such judicial review of democratically enacted legislation and policy making. Section 1 offers a brief conceptual sketch of the kind of epistemic democracy and the kind of international human rights courts of concern – in particular the European Court of Human Rights (ECtHR). Section 2 develops some of the relevant aspects of democratic theory: components of an epistemic justification for democratic majority rule, namely to determine whether proposed policy and legislation bundles are just, and providing assurance thereof. Several critical premises and scope conditions are noted in section 3. Section 4 considers the case(s) for international judicial review, arguing that such review helps secure those premises and scope conditions. The section goes on to consider the scope such review should have – and some objections to such an account. |
Follesdal, Andreas: Theories of Human Rights: Political or Orthodox – why it matters. In: Maliks, Reidar; Karlsson, Johan Schaffer (Ed.): Moral and Political Conceptions of Human Rights: Implications for Theory and Practice, pp. 77-96, Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, 2017. (Type: Book Chapter | Abstract | Links | Tags: Human Rights)@inbook{RN50170, One important contribution by a philosophical theory of international legal human rights [ILHR] is to provide normative perspectives and standards to assess the current international human rights regimes. .. There is currently a discussion about how two families of theories may best be used to develop such a philosophical theory of ILHR. ..”Orthodox” philosophical accounts .. tend to hold that behind the human rights movement generally – including ILHR – there is a unitary, cogent notion of moral human rights. .. “Political” theories pursue another aim and justificatory strategy. They aspire to systematize the existing international legal human rights practice, and seek to end with a theory with sufficient critical standards, – without drawing on a prior concept of a human right. … The aim of this article is primarily to alleviate some of the alleged conflicts, in particular to defend at least one Political theory against charges that it is unduly constrained to actual consensus on premises in defense of ILHR, that it is too closely linked to the current state system to match the universal ambitions of human rights, and that it seeks to avoid normative premises. |
Follesdal, Andreas: Law making by law breaking? A theory of parliamentary civil disobedience against international human rights courts. In: Saul, Matthew; Follesdal, Andreas; Ulfstein, Geir (Ed.): The International Human Rights Judiciary and National Parliaments: Europe and Beyond, pp. 329-352, Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, 2017. (Type: Book Chapter | Abstract | Links | Tags: Civil disobedience, European Court of Human Rights, Human Rights, International courts, Publications)@inbook{RN50106, Recent cases of non-compliance with judgments of the European Court of Human Rights (ECtHR) raise several profound questions of legitimacy. Some states seem simply unwilling to defer to the ECtHR, putting their own legitimacy on the line. Other cases, such as the Hirst v. UK case of prisoners’ voting rights, seem to challenge the legitimacy of the Court or aspects of its practices. May some such non-compliance with international courts in fact be justifiable? The present chapter argues that some forms of parliamentary disobedience may be understood and assessed not only as protest and avoidance, but also as a constructive mode of correcting the law making of the ECtHR. Under some conditions, certain forms of domestic parliamentary disobedience should be considered as and accepted as an extreme form of multi-level law making. Few states can be expected to pressure human rights ICs to interpret the treaties expansively. Thus states might not be suitable actors in a system of checks to ensure that ICs interpret in appropriate ways. Yet checks and balances should be developed in our multi-level legal order to alleviate the risks wrought by ICs’ interpretation and law making. |
Follesdal, Andreas: Independent yet Accountable: Stress Test Lessons for the European Court of Human Rights. In: Maastricht Journal of European and Comparative Law, vol. 24, no. 4, pp. 484-510, 2017. (Type: Journal Article | Abstract | Links | Tags: European Court of Human Rights, Human Rights)@article{RN50477, An important ‘stress test’ for regional human rights courts would be to see how well such courts perform when faced with authoritarian, human rights-violating regimes that they are supposed to hinder or constrain. These states are not only subjects of the court, but also its masters insofar as they enjoy various forms of control and accountability mechanisms that may constrain the court’s independence. The article argues that, at least in the case of the European Court of Human Rights (ECtHR), its precarious ‘constrained independence’ should be modified to enhance its impact even under such circumstances. Such changes could strengthen the ECtHR’s impartial and independent role without running the risk of turning it into a so-called ‘juristocracy’ – subjecting European states to the arbitrary rule of international judges. |
Follesdal, Andreas: Getting to Justice? On Albert Weale: Democratic Justice. In: Critical Review of International Social and Political Philosophy, vol. 20, no. 2, pp. 231-242, 2017. (Type: Journal Article | Abstract | Links | Tags: Gender, Publications)@article{RN50144, This article focuses on how Weale’s view in Democratic Justice (Oxford University Press 2013) fits into and responds to two strands of social contract traditions and their critics: the contractarian tradition as he claims to, which seeks to justify normative principles of justice from non-moral premises. The alternative is the contractualist tradition which assumes that individuals are also motivated by other-regarding moral considerations. The aim of the latter is often limited to systematize and specify vague and contested normative judgments concerning shared institutions. There are tensions in Weale’s book whether it addresses the question of concern to contractarians or that of contractualists. A second question concerns Weale’s attempt to extrapolate principles of justice from common property resource regimes within the basic structure of society to that basic structure of a ‘great society’ itself. The impact of the basic structure on individuals is so pervasive that the principle Weale proposes appears to be misapplied. A claim to the marginal product in complex modes of production supplemented by a social insurance scheme says little about the distributive principles for assessing how the basic structure should engender the distribution of marginal products among us. |
Follesdal, Andreas: Exporting the Margin of Appreciation: Lessons for the Inter-American Court of Human Rights?. In: International journal of constitutional law, vol. 15, no. 2, pp. 359-371, 2017. (Type: Journal Article | Abstract | Links | Tags: European Court of Human Rights, Human Rights, Margin of Appreciation)@article{RN50633, What might the Inter-American Court of Human Rights (IACtHR) gain from a ‘judicial dialogue’ with the European Court of Human Rights (ECtHR) in the form of borrowing the ECtHR’s margin of appreciation doctrine? Arguably, a favorable interpretation of the vague margin of appreciation doctrine allows the ECtHR to provide both human rights protection and deference to domestic democratic decision-making. This may guide the IACtHR’s attempt to respect both the American Convention on Human Rights and its sovereign creators. In particular, the ECtHR’s Doctrine may illustrate how these regional courts can interact with states that violate the respective conventions after less than fully democratic processes—in the eyes of the courts. The same margin of appreciation doctrine may justify more or less sovereignty-invading stances by both the IACtHR and by the ECtHR, depending on to the different levels of entrenchment of a democratic culture and rule of law in the state of concern, and depending on the actual deliberations carried out in the particular case. |
Follesdal, Andreas: Democracy and regional human rights courts: Enemies, allies, or both? Symposium. International Journal of Constitutional Law, 2017. (Type: Book | Abstract | Links | Tags: Democratic theory, Human Rights, Publications, Special issues)@book{RN50782, The regional human rights courts in Europe and the Americas have a complex relationship with democracy. On the one hand, they were established to protect democracy (and the fundamental rights on which democracy depends) and to serve as “alarm bells” to facilitate detection and early intervention if tyranny nevertheless threatened. On the other hand, however, specific procedures and practices of these courts, or certain forms of adjudicative activity, may threaten or undermine stable democratic self-governance. History has shown that the work of the European and Inter-American courts has, at times, both augmented and challenged democracy in their respective member jurisdictions. This symposium addresses certain aspects of this tension…. |
Follesdal, Andreas: Democracy and regional human rights courts. In: International Journal of Constitutional Law, vol. 15, no. 2, pp. 358, 2017. (Type: Journal Article | Abstract | Links | Tags: Democratic theory, Human Rights, Publications)@article{RN50781, The regional human rights courts in Europe and the Americas have a complex relationship with democracy. On the one hand, they were established to protect democracy (and the fundamental rights on which democracy depends) and to serve as “alarm bells” to facilitate detection and early intervention if tyranny nevertheless threatened. On the other hand, however, specific procedures and practices of these courts, or certain forms of adjudicative activity, may threaten or undermine stable democratic self-governance. History has shown that the work of the European and Inter-American courts has, at times, both augmented and challenged democracy in their respective member jurisdictions. This symposium addresses certain aspects of this tension…. |
Follesdal, Andreas; Tsereteli, Nino: The margin of appreciation in Europe and beyond – Special Issue. The International Journal of Human Rights, 2016. (Type: Book | Abstract | Tags: European Court of Human Rights, Human Rights, International courts, Margin of Appreciation, Special issues)@book{RN50638, Is the margin of appreciation doctrine of the European Court of Human Rights (ECtHR) a promising model of deference by a regional human rights court towards democratic states? Or does this doctrine amount to an abdication by such courts from their proper tasks of protecting human rights against violations by states? This special section contributes to the ongoing scholarly debate about the margin of appreciation doctrine, originally developed by the ECtHR. It also explores the emergence of similar doctrines of deference in human rights adjudication outside Europe. The four articles also raise issues relevant for a broader debate about legitimacy and effectiveness of international courts. The authors cover a number of courts, well-established as well as relatively young ones, operating in different legal and political contexts. It allows reflecting on common as well as courtspecific reasons for exercising or avoiding deference. |
Ulfstein, Geir: The European Court of Human Rights and national courts: a constitutional relationship?. In: Arnardóttir, Oddný Mjöll; Buyse, Antoine (Ed.): Shifting Centres of Gravity in Human Rights Protection, pp. 46-56, Routledge, London, 2016. (Type: Book Chapter | Tags: Human Rights)@inbook{RN50637, |
Follesdal, Andreas; Tsereteli, Nino: The margin of appreciation in Europe and beyond. In: The International Journal of Human Rights, vol. 20, no. 8, pp. 1055-1057, 2016. (Type: Journal Article | Abstract | Links | Tags: European Court of Human Rights, Human Rights, International courts, Margin of Appreciation, Publications)@article{RN50636, Is the margin of appreciation doctrine of the European Court of Human Rights (ECtHR) a promising model of deference by a regional human rights court towards democratic states? Or does this doctrine amount to an abdication by such courts from their proper tasks of protecting human rights against violations by states? This special section contributes to the ongoing scholarly debate about the margin of appreciation doctrine, originally developed by the ECtHR. It also explores the emergence of similar doctrines of deference in human rights adjudication outside Europe. The four articles also raise issues relevant for a broader debate about legitimacy and effectiveness of international courts. The authors cover a number of courts, well-established as well as relatively young ones, operating in different legal and political contexts. It allows reflecting on common as well as courtspecific reasons for exercising or avoiding deference. |
Follesdal, Andreas: Subsidiarity to the Rescue for the European Courts? Resolving tensions between the Margin of Appreciation and Human Rights Protection. In: Heidemann, Dietmar; Stoppenbrink, Katja (Ed.): Join, or Die – Philosophical Foundations of Federalism, pp. 251-272, de Gruyter, Berlin, 2016. (Type: Book Chapter | Abstract | Links | Tags: EU – European Union, European Court of Human Rights, Federalism, Human Rights, Margin of Appreciation, Publications, Subsidiarity)@inbook{RN50196, Protests against how the European Court of Human Rights manages the dilemma between protecting human rights and respecting sovereignty led to Protocol 15, which includes references to ‘subsidiarity and a ‘margin of appreciation’ in the Preamble to the European Convention on Human Rights. The article argues that a ‘Principle of Subsidiarity’ can alleviate some of the challenges posed by the margin of appreciation doctrine, in particular that it sacrifices human rights protection on the altar of respect for state sovereignty. Section 1 presents the Margin of appreciation doctrine and some criticism raised against it, section 2 sketches versions of the principle of subsidiarity relevant for this discussion. Section 3 seeks to bring subsidiarity to bear on the question of which authority the ECtHR should enjoy within a multi-level European legal order, and in particular why it should grant states a certain margin of appreciation. Section 4 considers how these arguments concerning a margin of appreciation applies to the European Union—leaving the many other aspects of accession aside. |
Follesdal, Andreas: Subsidiarity and international human rights courts: respecting self-governance and protecting human rights – or neither?. In: Law and Contemporary Problems, vol. 79, no. 2, pp. 147-163, 2016. (Type: Journal Article | Abstract | Links | Tags: European Court of Human Rights, Human Rights, International courts, Margin of Appreciation, Publications, Subsidiarity)@article{RN50076, Several regional and international courts (ICs) and treaty bodies are empowered to review whether a state’s legislation and policies are consistent with the human-rights conventions it has signed. This article considers how subsidiarity may be brought to bear on the challenges the ECtHR and the IACtHR face. The article focuses on two politically salient, normative questions. First, should states— even well-functioning democracies—subject themselves to ICs with the authority to interpret and adjudicate alleged violations of relevant human-rights treaties? Second, is it is consistent with their mission of protecting human rights that ICs grant the states some discretion, that is, a “margin of appreciation,” or does such discretion nullify the human-rights protection the ICs were established to provide? The discussion of these ICs lends support to several of the assumptions concerning subsidiarity outlined in this issue’s introduction. |
Follesdal, Andreas: Squaring the Circle at the Battle at Brighton: Is the War between protecting human rights or respecting sovereignty over, or has it just begun?. In: Arnardóttir, Oddný Mjöll; Buyse, Antoine (Ed.): Shifting Centres of Gravity in Human Rights Protection: Rethinking Relations between the ECHR, EU, and National Legal Orders, pp. 189-204, Routledge, London, 2016. (Type: Book Chapter | Abstract | Links | Tags: European Consensus, European Court of Human Rights, Human Rights, Margin of Appreciation, Publications, Subsidiarity)@inbook{RN50034, How should the European Court of Human Rights best ‘balance’ respect for the sovereignty of states with protection of the human rights of their citizens? The Court’s theory of subsidiarity must inform its margin of appreciation doctrine when Protocol 15 includes these two concepts in the Preamble of the European Convention on Human Rights. Issues for the Court and for researchers include aspects the doctrine of the margin of appreciation: the proportionality test and the ‘European consensus’; and a more justifiable conception of subsidiarity. |
Follesdal, Andreas: Implications of contested multilateralism for global constitutionalism. In: Global Constitutionalism, vol. 5, no. 3, pp. 297-308, 2016. (Type: Journal Article | Abstract | Links | Tags: )@article{RN50261, The term ‘global constitutionalism’ has been used in various ways, all of which may be appropriate for different purposes. The first sections therefore specify some salient features of that term and of ‘constitutional pluralism’ – before turning to three implications of Morse and Keohane’s claims about ‘contested multilateralism’ (CM) for global constitutionalism, including new forms of constitutional pluralism. The focus is primarily on aspects of CM regarded as a mode of constitutional change, considering what to make of such a form of ‘extra-constitutional’ procedure. Research challenges for political science, law and normative political theory are identified. Challenges by CM to the stability of international law are argued to be overdrawn. Of greater concern is that CM lends itself to piecemeal adjustments rather than reforms with an eye to the systemic effects. However, these worries must be tempered by the non-ideal nature of the present legal structure which should make us wary of imposing normative standards drawn from settings where institutions are fully just and generally complied with. |
Follesdal, Andreas: Building democracy at the bar: The European Court of Human Rights as an agent of transitional cosmopolitanism. In: Transnational Legal Theory, no. special issue, ed. Claudio Corradetti, pp. 95-113, 2016. (Type: Journal Article | Abstract | Links | Tags: Democratic theory, European Consensus, European Court of Human Rights, Human Rights, Publications)@article{RN50171, How, if at all, does the European Court of Human Rights (ECtHR) promote more just states which vary greatly in their democratic credentials? The article considers the ECtHR and its practices from the perspective of ‘non-ideal theory,’ namely how it helps states become more stable and just, and more compliant with the human rights norms of the European Convention on Human Rights. The article first sketches what is meant by ‘non-ideal theory,’ then considers aspects of the Council of Europe and the ECtHR which promote transitions toward more just member states. The ECtHR’s practices suffer from at least two weaknesses in this regard: it assumes with insufficient argument that standards appropriate for ‘ideal theory’ conditions of full compliance also should apply to states that suffer from wide ranging noncompliance, or from unjust institutions. Secondly, the Court relies on an ‘emerging European consensus’ with insufficient empirical and normative justification. |
Follesdal, Andreas; Muniz-Fraticelli, Victor: The Principle of Subsidiarity as a constitutional principle in the EU and Canada. In: Les Ateliers de l’Éthique/The Ethics Forum, vol. 10, no. 2, pp. 89-206, 2015. (Type: Journal Article | Abstract | Links | Tags: Human Rights, Publications, Subsidiarity)@article{RN49342, A Principle of Subsidiarity regulates the allocation and/or use of authority within a political order where authority is dispersed between a centre and various sub-units. Section one sketches the role of such principle of subsidiarity in the EU, and some of its significance in Canada. Section 2 presents some conceptions of subsidiarity that indicate the range of alternatives. Section 3 considers some areas where such conceptions might add value to constitutional and political deliberations in Canada. Section 4 concludes with some reminders of crucial contested issues not fully resolved by appeals to subsidiarity alone, exemplified by the protection of human rights. |
Follesdal, Andreas: Social Primary Goods. In: Mandle, Jon; Reidy, David (Ed.): The Cambridge Rawls Lexicon, pp. 643-647, Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, 2015. (Type: Book Chapter | Abstract | Links | Tags: Gender, John Rawls, Publications)@inbook{RN49151, Rawls’ theory of justice concerns the scope of required equalities and permitted inequalities engendered by the basic social structure (BS) of a society. this subject requires an index of benefits and burdens that allows publicly accessible interpersonal comparisons of citizens’ well-being, in the relevant sense, among representative members of various social groups. Rawls’ answer is to focus on how the basic structure of society distributes Social primary goods. The entry discusses this account. |
Follesdal, Andreas: Machiavelli at 500: From Cynic to Vigilant Supporter of International Law. In: Ratio Juris, vol. 28, no. 2, pp. 242-51, 2015. (Type: Journal Article | Abstract | Links | Tags: International courts, Publications)@article{RN50023, Machiavelli’s 500 year old treatise The Prince laid out central features of the realist tradition in international relations. His premises led him to question the likelihood of efficacious and stable international law and international courts, a scepticism that has present day proponents. Machiavelli’s reluctance was due to a combination of features of human nature and a focus on anarchic features of the relations among states. The article challenges these assumptions and implications: other interpretations of human nature are closer to Machiavelli’s text, and the current relations among states are significantly different. The revised assumptions should render Machiavelli’s followers more optimistic about international law and international courts. |
Follesdal, Andreas: International Human Rights Courts: Beyond a State of Nature – Foreword. In: Ajevski, Marjan (Ed.): Fragmentation in International Human Rights Law: Beyond Conflicts of Laws, pp. xi-xviii, Routledge, London, 2015. (Type: Book Chapter | Abstract | Links | Tags: Human Rights)@inbook{RN50083, The subject of this fascinating volume is the fragmentation of international and regional human rights courts and treaty bodies (ICs), that is, tensions among courts which all address the same functional area, often bringing apparently similar norms to bear. The rights of concern here are widely regarded as belonging to the core of human rights: freedom of expression, right to privacy, freedom of assembly, and freedom of association. What are we to make of the conflicts that occur not only among such rights and other norms of international law – ranging from trade to the environment – but conflicts among the various human rights courts empower to adjudicate such rights – which courts and rights often conflict? |
Follesdal, Andreas: Curb, Channel and Coordinate: The Constitutionalisation of International Courts and Tribunals. In: Baere, Geert De; Wouters, Jan (Ed.): The Contribution of International and Supranational Courts to the Rule of Law, pp. 355-369, Elgar Publishing, Cheltenham, 2015. (Type: Book Chapter | Abstract | Links | Tags: EU – European Union, Human Rights, International courts, Publications, Subsidiarity)@inbook{RN50186, From the vantage point of normative political philosophy the preceding chapters in this volume offer several lessons and further research questions of how to assess and promote the legitimacy of these ICs. The following comments identify some of these. Several proposals amount to measures of constitutionalisation of ICs. Section I identifies some of the hitherto understudied arenas where the authors remind us that the perceived legitimacy of the ICs matters if they are to secure their various objectives. Section II addresses one central standard of legitimacy: the content of the concept of the Rule of Law, which remains contested both as an objective of ICs, and as a requirement on their operation. I stipulate that two central underlying values justify several if not all rule of law norms: non-domination and stable legitimate expectations. Respect for human rights is a further substantive value which many but not all contributors include in the concept. I then consider two main challenges to the legitimacy of ICs from rule of law standards. One is the possible fragmentation and the legal uncertainty that may ensue. Section III thus summarizes the chapters’ insights about the alleged fragmentation wrought by so many ICs. Section IV considers some further challenges to the objectives and performance of ICs by these rule of law standards. Their multiple objectives require that the judges and arbitrators enjoy a wide berth of discretion in interpretation and adjudication – which raise the risk that states and individuals become subject to domination by the ICs themselves. Individuals may end up not living under the rule of law but under the rule of international lawyers. The following two sections gather several possible strands of responses to these fears. Section V elaborates how the power of ICs is constrained by their complex interrelationship with domestic authorities. Some such interdependence may be assessed by a further popular standard of legitimacy in addition to the rule of law, namely subsidiarity. This concept is often invoked in international law, explicitly so for the European Union4 and in debates concerning the European Convention on Human Rights.5 The section explores how several features of the authority of ICs presented by the authors may be explained and perhaps assessed by some standard of subsidiarity, to reduce the risks wrought by the ICs themselves. Appeals to subsidiarity may not so much lay issues to rest as stimulate more structured and systematic arguments concerning the legitimacy of ICs. Section VI considers several ways to regulate the discretion of the ICs to reduce the risks of fragmentation and domination, garnered from the contributions of this volume. Increased legitimacy of international courts requires perspectives and measures of constitutionalisation: Promote rule of law standards by better checks on the international courts, and channel and coordinate them better. |
Ajevski, Marjan: Fragmentation in International Human Rights Law: Beyond Conflicts of Laws. Routledge, London, 2015. (Type: Book | Abstract | Links | Tags: Human Rights)@book{RN50234, The subject of this fascinating volume is the fragmentation of international and regional human rights courts and treaty bodies (ICs), that is, tensions among courts which all address the same functional area, often bringing apparently similar norms to bear. The rights of concern here are widely regarded as belonging to the core of human rights: freedom of expression, right to privacy, freedom of assembly, and freedom of association. What are we to make of the conflicts that occur not only among such rights and other norms of international law – ranging from trade to the environment – but conflicts among the various human rights courts empower to adjudicate such rights – which courts and rights often conflict? |
Follesdal, Andreas: Subsidiarity and the global order. In: Zimmermann, Augusto; Evans, Michelle (Ed.): Global Perspectives on Subsidiarity, pp. 207-220, Springer, Dordrecht, 2014. (Type: Book Chapter | Abstract | Links | Tags: EU – European Union, European Court of Human Rights, Human Rights, Publications, Subsidiarity)@inbook{RN55344, Subsidiarity has been proposed as an answer to the challenges of globalization and global governance. This chapter addresses some of the strengths and weaknesses of such a principle of subsidiarity for questions of how to allocate and use authority at regional and global levels. The chapter criticizes the ‘state centric’ versions of subsidiarity often appealed to for such global settings. In particular, there are several challenges wrought by states that fail to respect their citizens’ human rights, variously interpreted. More defensible versions of subsidiarity do not provide normative legitimacy to the state centric aspects of the global order. Section 1 sketches some of the remarkably different conceptions of subsidiarity as a background to the usages in the European Union, the Catholic Church and as it allegedly appears in international law. The different versions drastically reduce or enlarge the scope of member unit authority. Section 2 considers some implications for the legitimate allocation of authority in our global order which includes many states that routinely violate their citizens’ fundamental human rights. The function of the European Court of Human Rights offers a helpful contrast. |
Follesdal, Andreas: Engagement, divestment, or both? Conflicts and interactions: The case of the Norwegian Pension Fund. In: Bohoslavsky, Juan Pablo; Cernic, Jernej Letnar (Ed.): Sovereign Financing, pp. 323-336, Hart, Oxford, 2014. (Type: Book Chapter | Abstract | Links | Tags: Human Rights, Public policy, Publications, SRI – Socially responsible investing)@inbook{RN49321, The Norwegian Government Pension Fund is often regarded as the largest sovereign wealth fund in the world. The Fund merits international attention not only because of its size, but also in terms of its complex mission with regard to responsible investment and the mechanisms it employs in pursuit of this mission. At the same time, the Norwegian Parliament does not want the Fund to contribute to unethical acts or omissions, such as violations of fundamental humanitarian principles, serious violations of human rights, gross corruption or severe environmental damage. It has established two main mechanisms to avoid such complicity. These mechanisms ensure that the Fund is involved in ‘Socially Responsible Investing’ (SRI) of two distinct kinds: An activist approach and a negative approach. The following sections explore these mechanisms and discusses tensions among them, against a historic and current background. |
Ulfstein, Geir; Follesdal, Andreas: The European Court of Human Rights and the Norwegian Supreme Court – Independence and Democratic Control. In: Engstad, Nils Asbjørn; Frøseth, Astrid Lærdal; Tønder, Bård (Ed.): The Independence of Judges, pp. 247-260, Eleven, 2014. (Type: Book Chapter | Abstract | Links | Tags: European Court of Human Rights, Human Rights)@inbook{RN49702, How far the courts should go in testing legislation has been highlighted in Norway in recent years by several cases where the Supreme Court has deemed laws unconstitutional. Critics claim that courts thus interfere with democratic decision-making, whilst protecting neither the rule of law nor vulnerable population groups.2 The empowerment of courts means that the independence and qualifications of the judges become more important. It furthermore adds to ‘legalization’, which increasingly causes popular and political concern. The internationalization of law raises further issues for judicial review. In this article, we discuss review of national law on the basis of the European Convention on Human Rights (ECHR) by the European Court of Human Rights (ECtHR) and by the Norwegian Supreme Court. We are concerned both with the possible democratic legitimacy of such review, and other grounds for legitimacy. We finally point to some implications of this internationalization of law for public perceptions of the judges’ functions in society and for their independence – and some implications for the Norwegian selection of judges to the Supreme Court and the ECtHR. |
Maliks, Reidar; Follesdal, Andreas: Kantian theory and human rights. In: Follesdal, Andreas; Maliks, Reidar (Ed.): Kantian theory and human rights, pp. 1-7, Routledge, 2014. (Type: Book Chapter | Abstract | Links | Tags: Human Rights)@inbook{RN49801, It is, perhaps, not by chance that the steep increase in theories of human rights has been matched by a renaissance in studies of Kant’s political philosophy. The essays are animated by the idea that if we get a better grip on Kant’s philosophy of right, we can energize the creative endeavor of developing philosophical theories of human rights, inspired by his particular way of thinking about the relation between rights and the rule of law. Three features characteristic of Kant’s thinking frequently crop up in the following chapters and help explain why so much recent scholarship may indeed properly be called ‘Kantian’. These features concern rights, legitimacy, and institutions. freedom is constituted by the rights and duties that enable individuals to be subject to the rule of law instead of arbitrary power. Second, political and legal authorities that establish human rights through law derive their legitimacy from being capable of justification to individuals. Third, the public institutions at the domestic and the international level are considered part of the same system. The contributions explore these Kantian principles in different directions. |
Føllesdal, Andreas: Hvis det norske forbudet mot dobbelt statsborgerskap er løsningen, hva er da problemet?. In: Langeland, Nils Rune (Ed.): Politisk kompetanse: grunnlovas borgar 1814-2014, pp. 78-87, Pax, Oslo, 2014. (Type: Book Chapter | Abstract | Links | Tags: )@inbook{RN49330, Hva slags kompetanse bør stemmeberettigede borgere ha? Hva bør de kunne, og hva bør de være lojale mot når de skal ha stemmerett til stortingsvalg? Blant reglene som setter disse spørsmålene på spissen, er forbudet mot dobbelt statsborgerskap i statsborgerloven av 2005. Forarbeidene til loven drøfter disse sentrale spørsmålene om politisk kompetanse og trekker flere konsekvenser. Argumentene fremført til forsvar for forbudet holder ikke mål. Det er derfor vanskelig å se hvilke legitime interesser staten har av dette forbudet, ikke minst fordi påståtte ulemper med dobbelt politisk lojalitet er dårlig begrunnet, og fordi forbudet ser ut til å hemme integrering, i strid med målsettingen. |
Føllesdal, Andreas: Del av problemet, og del av løsningen: Den europeiske menneskerettighetsdomstolen og demokratisk selvstyre. In: Baldersheim, Harald; Østerud, Øyvind (Ed.): Det norske demokratiet i det 21. århundre, pp. 80-91, Fagbokforlaget, Oslo, 2014. (Type: Book Chapter | Abstract | Links | Tags: )@inbook{RN49917, For å forstå og vurdere bekymringene for fremveksten av internasjonale domstoler og domstolsliknende organer er det viktig å se hvordan de griper inn i og preger nasjonale domstoler og myndigheter. Bidrar slike domstoler til å undergrave det nasjonale demokratiske selvstyre, og i så fall: hvordan skjer det, og hva skal vi synes om dette? Artikkelen ser på ett av flere viktige områder der disse spørsmålene melder seg, nemlig om og hvordan den europeiske menneskerettighetsdomstolen respekterer nasjonale demokratiske beslutninger der det kan se ut som de bryter med den europeiske menneskerettighetskonvensjon. |
Follesdal, Andreas; Maliks, Reidar: Kantian theory and human rights. Routledge, 2014. (Type: Book | Abstract | Links | Tags: Edited books, Human Rights)@book{RN49725, Human rights and the courts and tribunals that protect them are increasingly part of our moral, legal, and political circumstances. The growing salience of human rights has recently brought the question of their philosophical foundation to the foreground. Theorists of human rights often assume that their ideal can be traced to the philosophy of Immanuel Kant and his view of humans as ends in themselves. Yet, few have attempted to explore exactly how human rights should be understood in a Kantian framework. The scholars in this book have gathered to fill this gap. At the center of Kant’s theory of rights is a view of freedom as independence from domination. The chapters explore the significance of this theory for the nature of human rights, their justification, and the legitimacy of international human rights courts. |
Follesdal, Andreas: Subsidiarity and the global order. In: Zimmermann, Augusto; Evans, Michelle (Ed.): Global Perspectives on Subsidiarity, pp. 207-220, Springer, Dordrecht, 2014. (Type: Book Chapter | Abstract | Links | Tags: European Court of Human Rights, Human Rights)@inbook{RN49328, Subsidiarity has been proposed as an answer to the challenges of globalization and global governance. This chapter addresses some of the strengths and weaknesses of such a principle of subsidiarity for questions of how to allocate and use authority at regional and global levels. The chapter criticizes the ‘state centric’ versions of subsidiarity often appealed to for such global settings. In particular, there are several challenges wrought by states that fail to respect their citizens’ human rights, variously interpreted. More defensible versions of subsidiarity do not provide normative legitimacy to the state centric aspects of the global order. Section 1 sketches some of the remarkably different conceptions of subsidiarity as a background to the usages in the European Union, the Catholic Church and as it allegedly appears in international law. The different versions drastically reduce or enlarge the scope of member unit authority. Section 2 considers some implications for the legitimate allocation of authority in our global order which includes many states that routinely violate their citizens’ fundamental human rights. The function of the European Court of Human Rights offers a helpful contrast. |
Follesdal, Andreas: Okin, Susan. In: Gibbons, Michael; Coole, Diana; Ellis, Elisabeth (Ed.): Encyclopedia of Political Thought, Wiley-Blackwell, 2014, ISBN: 978-1-4051-9129-6. (Type: Book Chapter | Abstract | Links | Tags: Gender, Publications)@inbook{RN49244, Susan Moller Okin, an egalitarian feminist liberal, reconstructed the history of political thought to correct for the absence, exclusion or distortion of women, gendered culture and reproduction. She developed the social contract tradition to secure family and gender central place, highlighted the plight of minority women in multicultural societies, and contributed to women-centred development policies. |
Follesdal, Andreas: Legitimacy Challenges and what to do about them – Accountability and authority of the European Court of Human Rights. In: Proceedings of Conference on the Long-term future of the European Court of Human Rights, pp. 78-85, 2014. (Type: Journal Article | Abstract | Links | Tags: European Court of Human Rights, Human Rights, Margin of Appreciation)@article{RN49901, For this session on accountability, four concerns about the ECtHR merit mention: – the Court’s backlog of well-founded cases; – allegations of overly dynamic interpretation by power-hungry judges; – criticism that the Court abdicates by granting powerful states a margin of appreciation; – criticism that the Court lacks due deference toward well-functioning democracies. …. |
Follesdal, Andreas: Kant, Human Rights, and Courts. In: Follesdal, Andreas; Maliks, Reidar (Ed.): Kantian theory and human rights, pp. 193-202, Routledge, 2014. (Type: Book Chapter | Abstract | Links | Tags: Human Rights, International courts, Publications)@inbook{RN49802, why we should go back to Kant when we seek to understand human rights as they exist in today’s globalized world. It is a good question: why turn once again to a dead white European man for answers to our own questions? The social and legal setting of his day differed so much from ours that we may well wonder what his thoughts might contribute to our world. .. It is in order to understand the puzzles raised by human rights principles and institutions that the essays in this volume develop thinking that is Kantian, that is, inspired by his particular way of thinking about the relation between rights and the rule of law. The following are some reflections prompted by these contributions. The first section explores the role of theories of human rights law, the second section explores the unit of analysis, whether it should be courts or the global basic structure. Section three asks whether international courts suffer a democratic deficit worth worrying about; section four addresses prescriptions – what institutional mechanisms would suffice for legitimacy; section five asks what should guide the discretion of judges of international courts, while section six suggests some remaining ‘Kantian’ issues to be explored. |
Follesdal, Andreas: John Rawls’ Theory of Justice as Fairness. In: Fløistad, Guttorm (Ed.): Philosophy of Justice, pp. 311-328, Springer, Dordrecht, 2014. (Type: Book Chapter | Abstract | Links | Tags: John Rawls)@inbook{RN49430, When do citizens have a moral duty to obey the government and support the institutions of society? This question is central to political philosophy. One of the 20 century’s main response was John Rawls’ theory of justice, “Justice as fairness”, in the book A Theory of Justice, published 1971. The book Justice as Fairness was an improved and shorter presentation of Rawls’ theory, published 2001 with editorial support by Erin Kelly, one of his former students. …This introduction of Rawls falls into eight parts. After a brief biographical introduction, Part 2 presents the allocation principles he advocated. Part 3 presents Rawls’ conception of society and the individual, as an introduction to the rest of the argument presented in part 4 Section 5 takes up his theory of justification, and part 6 points to three areas where the more recent book Justice as Fairness differs somewhat from A Theory of Justice. Section 7 presents some of the criticisms that have been raised, and section 8 points to some lasting contributions of Rawls’ theory. |
Follesdal, Andreas: Guiding and guarding international judges. In: New York University School of Law Journal of International Law and Politics, vol. 46, no. 3, pp. 793-808, 2014. (Type: Journal Article | Links | Tags: )@article{RN49688, |
Follesdal, Andreas: Global Citizenship. In: Sterri, Aksel Braanen (Ed.): Global Citizen – Challenges and Responsibility in an Interconnected World, pp. 71-82, Sense, Rotterdam, 2014. (Type: Book Chapter | Abstract | Links | Tags: Human Rights)@inbook{RN49722, Our actions and practices increasingly mutually affect others across territorial borders. Since these processes of globalization affect our opportunities and our possible impact, globalization also affects what we ought to do – as ‘global citizens’. The chapter explores some implications for our conceptions of citizenship beyond the state. Individuals should be able to exercise some democratic voting rights and some human rights vis-à-vis governance structures above the nation state under our conditions of globalization. After a brief overview including a historical backdrop, section 2 sketches some components of global citizenship, and section 3 considers several objections to this notion. |
Follesdal, Andreas: Federalism and Human Rights in Nepal’s Constitutional Design: Challenges for the Judiciary. In: Ehlers, Dirk; Glaser, Hennig; Prokati, Kittisak (Ed.): Constitutionalism and good governance: Western and Eastern perspectives, vol. 1, pp. 193-203, Nomos, Baden Baden, 2014. (Type: Book Chapter | Abstract | Links | Tags: Federalism, Human Rights, Nepal, Publications)@inbook{RN49661, The article addresses one of the difficult tasks of the Nepal Judiciary, which it shares in part with the Constituent Assembly: how to interpret the idea and mechanisms of federalism in ways that are faithful to the best interests of the Nepal people. The CA must create the constitution of a democratic, human rights-respecting Nepal republic, in light of how the constitution will in turn be interpreted and applied by the judiciary. The reflections in this article concern four varieties of federal elements, discussing arguments in favor and against each drawn from an interpretation of other states’ experiences. Two of the four are territorial: Constitutional – an entrenched split of powers – and Political: decentralised autonomy. Two are non-territorial: Minority Rights, and Minority Representation in common decision making bodies. Some of these arguments and lessons may be helpful also for Nepal’s challenges, two features of which are especially noteworthy: there are very many different groups that must be accommodated fairly. And members of these groups very often live side by side on the same territory. Human rights protections combined with federal elements of Nepal’s new constitution must serve to prevent future domination, especially by the centres, over these many ethnic groups and castes. The new constitution therefore creates several new tasks and challenges for Nepal’s judiciary, several of which are identified. |
Follesdal, Andreas: Democratic standards in an asymmetric Union. In: Cramme, Olaf; Hobolt, Sara B. (Ed.): Democratic Politics in a European Union under Stress, pp. 199 -216, Oxford University Press, Oxford, 2014. (Type: Book Chapter | Abstract | Links | Tags: Democratic theory, EU – European Union, Federalism, Publications)@inbook{RN49578, Throughout the present Eurozone crisis, worries about legitimacy and democracy have been particularly vocal, albeit often conflated, and not always very clear. What are we to make of such concerns, and the proposals brought forward? Discussions about the democratic deficit often target the wrong problems, either because the alleged problems are misinterpreted, or because they are in fact not problems at all. Nevertheless, it remains the case (and notwithstanding the contestability of some of the evidence) that the EU is insufficiently democratically accountable. While some weaknesses may be temporary, others seem to be more entrenched in the constitutional structure of the EU. In particular, we need to reconsider our democratic standards if the scholars who say that we must expect the EU to keep features of an asymmetrical federal order, with differentiated integration, are right. My comments concerning the prospects of a sufficiently legitimate EU are clustered under the rubrics of Symptoms, Diagnoses, Prescriptions, and Prognosis. |
Follesdal, Andreas: Democracy, identity, and European public spheres. In: Risse, Thomas (Ed.): European Public Spheres: Politics is Back, pp. 247-262, Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, 2014. (Type: Book Chapter | Abstract | Links | Tags: Democratic theory, EU – European Union, Publications)@inbook{RN49273, The empirical findings of this volume give evidence of Europeanisation in the form of political contestation about matters European. What is the significance for democracy and for the future European Union, of increased politicization in the sense of contestation in various public spheres among political parties about the European polity and regimes – including the territory and competences of the EU. I suggest that there is a third option, in addition to either unfortunate corrosion and fragmentation of the EU or “normalization” of policy contestation, namely permanent salient contestation about constitutional matters – of which the euro crisis may be only one. |
Follesdal, Andreas: Competing Conceptions of Subsidiarity. In: Fleming, James E.; Levy, Jacob T. (Ed.): Nomos LV: Federalism and Subsidiarity, pp. 214-230, New York University Press, New York, 2014. (Type: Book Chapter | Abstract | Links | Tags: European Court of Human Rights, Federalism, Human Rights, Publications, Subsidiarity)@inbook{RN49271, Appeals to a Principle of Subsidiarity has become popular due to its aspirations to address the allocation or use of authority within a political order, typically those where authority is dispersed between a centre and various member units. However, considerations of subsidiarity will seldom resolve disagreements about the allocation of authority. To illustrate how different conceptions of subsidiarity have profoundly different implications for constitutional and institutional design, the article first consider four different theories before turning to some implications as seen in the discussions about US federalism, debates in Europe about the EU and the European Court of Human Rights, and international law. |
Follesdal, Andreas: A common European identity for European citizenship?. In: German Law Journal, vol. 15, no. 5, pp. 765-775, 2014, (Nivå 1). (Type: Journal Article | Abstract | Links | Tags: Federalism, Publications)@article{RN49871, What sort of shared European identity is required for Union citizenship to be part of a sustainable, just European political and legal order? Which substantive values and beliefs should be shared? And is there a need for “unique” values and beliefs, exclusive among those who share citizenship? Section 1 affirms the need for some shared values. Section 2 explores aspects of such a shared identity. Section 3 denies the need for a shared “thick” cultural identity. Likewise, section 4 questions the need for unique values. Finally, section 5 points to several challenges concerning identity and citizenship in a Union with asymmetric federal elements, especially when it is subject to asymmetric shocks. |
Schaffer, Johan Karlsson; Follesdal, Andreas; Ulfstein, Geir: International human rights and the challenge of legitimacy. In: Follesdal, Andreas; Schaffer, Johan; Ulfstein, Geir (Ed.): The Legitimacy of International Human Rights Regimes, pp. 1-30, Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, 2013. (Type: Book Chapter | Abstract | Links | Tags: Human Rights)@inbook{RN49803, The practices and institutions of international human rights would seem to enjoy, on average, a broad, strong legitimacy in the contemporary world. And yet, on the other hand, international human rights practices increasingly face potentially disabling skepticism and critique, resentment and even resistance…this volume … contributes to an increasingly lively research literature spanning the disciplines of law, philosophy, political science and international relations. This introductory chapter serves, first, to give some examples of the type of political controversies over international human rights regimes that motivate this volume; second, to place the volume in current academic debates about international human rights and about the legitimate authority of international institutions; and thirdly, to outline the topics covered in the individual contributions. .. |
Follesdal, Andreas; Schaffer, Johan; Ulfstein, Geir: The Legitimacy of International Human Rights Regimes: Legal, Political and Philosophical Perspectives. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, 2013. (Type: Book | Abstract | Links | Tags: Edited books, Human Rights)@book{RN49346, this book brings together prominent scholars in law, political philosophy and international relations in order to address the legitimacy of international human rights regimes as a theoretically challenging and politically salient case of international authority. It provides a unique and thorough overview of the legitimacy problems involved in the global governance of human rights. |
Follesdal, Andreas; Peters, Birgit; Ulfstein, Geir: Introduction. In: Follesdal, Andreas; Peters, Birgit; Ulfstein, Geir (Ed.): Constituting Europe: The European Court of Human Rights in a National, European and Global Context, pp. 1-24, Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, 2013. (Type: Book Chapter | Abstract | Links | Tags: European Court of Human Rights, Human Rights)@inbook{RN49579, This book examines the new institutional settings of the Court. Few contributions have hitherto concentrated on these multiple relationships of the ECtHR…. The book aims to assess the relationship between the Court and the member states, the EU, the UN and the other organs of the Council of Europe, partly by referring to a specific set of normative criteria, and taking into consideration their respective needs and their own institutional functions. It seeks to provide a coherent overview and some more principled answers to the current reform debate and future design of the Court and of its relationship to the national, European and global level. The book’s main areas of consideration and main objectives are outlined in the following sections… |
Follesdal, Andreas; Peters, Birgit; Ulfstein, Geir: Constituting Europe: The European Court of Human Rights in a national, European and global context. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, 2013. (Type: Book | Abstract | Links | Tags: Edited books, European Court of Human Rights, Human Rights)@book{RN49345, At fifty, the European Court of Human Rights finds itself in a new institutional setting. With the EU joining the European Convention on Human Rights in the near future, and the Court increasingly having to address the responsibility of states in UN-lead military operations, the Court faces important challenges at the national, European and international levels. In light of recent reform discussions, this volume addresses the multi-level relations of the Court by drawing on existing debates, pointing to current deficits and highlighting the need for further improvements. |
Follesdal, Andreas; Peters, Birgit; Ulfstein, Geir: Conclusions. In: Follesdal, Andreas; Peters, Birgit; Ulfstein, Geir (Ed.): Constituting Europe: The European Court of Human Rights in a National, European and Global Context, pp. 389-402, Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, 2013. (Type: Book Chapter | Abstract | Links | Tags: European Court of Human Rights, Human Rights)@inbook{RN49580, …the member states, the organs of the Council of Europe – including the Court itself – the EU and, possibly, the UN, are still seeking to calibrate and develop the ECtHR’s legitimacy within the European sphere of fundamental rights. …. , it is difficult to deny the ECtHR’s constitutional role in its relations with the member states. This is not to say that the ECtHR is formally embedded in the general judicial review structure at the member state levels. Nonetheless, it decides on the compatibility of legislative as well as administrative and judicial acts with the Convention. Pilot judgment cases, in particular, may entail a declaration of incompatibility of particular legal provisions with the Convention … The Court’s Legitimacy….. Development and further solutions … The Future… |
Follesdal, Andreas: Subsidiarity as a Constitutional Principle in International Law. In: Global Constitutionalism, vol. 2, no. 1, pp. 37-62, 2013. (Type: Journal Article | Links | Tags: Publications, Subsidiarity)@article{RN49343, |
Follesdal, Andreas: Much ado about Nothing? International Judicial Review of Human Rights in Well Functioning Democracies. In: Follesdal, Andreas; Schaffer, Johan; Ulfstein, Geir (Ed.): The Legitimacy of International Human Rights Regimes, pp. 272-299, Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, 2013. (Type: Book Chapter | Abstract | Links | Tags: European Court of Human Rights, Human Rights)@inbook{RN49403, The chapter addresses some of the tensions between sovereignty, international human rights review and legitimacy, and bring these findings to bear on the proposals for reform of the European Court of Human Rights (ECtHR) that would reduce its authority over national legislatures and judiciaries. The objectives of such review are not obvious, the causes of noncompliance are contested, as is the legality of dynamic treaty interpretation; all of which hamper efforts to assess proposed improvements. Section 1 presents some relevant aspects of the ECtHR. Section 2 reviews some of the recent criticism against the ECtHR practice of judicial review to protect human rights in ‘well-functioning’ democracies, in terms of various forms of legitimacy deficits. It also presents some of the recent proposals for reform of the ECtHR. Section 3 lays out some reasons why such judicial review of majoritarian democratic decision-making may be defensible, also for well functioning democracies. Section 4 responds to some of the criticisms, and presents a partial defence. Some standard objections are not well targeted against the practices of the ECtHR, partly due to the division of responsibility between it and national public bodies, and the different roles of legislators and of judiciaries. Section 5 returns to the proposals presented in section 2. Section 6 concludes by considering some of the important remaining normative challenges, this partial defence notwithstanding. |
Follesdal, Andreas: Much Ado about Nothing? Claims about political appointment to the Norwegian Supreme Court – and what to do – and not to do – about it. In: Tidsskrift for rettsvitenskap, no. 3, pp. 365-371, 2013, (Grendstad). (Type: Journal Article | Abstract | Links | Tags: )@article{RN49509, Should recent reports of political appointments of Norwegian Supreme Court judges give rise to concern and reform of the process, e.g. toward more explicitly politicized hearings or vetting of nominees? Renewed attention to the patterns of political and ideological leanings among these judges should be welcome, and some observed patterns seem plausible. Insofar as such patterns can be identified, it may seem misplaced to criticize Grendstad et al for overlooking the differences in procedures for selecting judges and the different judicial cultures, e.g. between the US and Norway. If there are statistically significant correlations, the appropriate response may well be to explore possible mechanisms – different from those in full view in the US. But the recent research findings that allege a politicized appointment process can be improved in at least two ways. I shall argue in section 1 that the evidence Grendstad et al present for such ‘political’ appointments is weak. Section 2 suggests that more dimensions than political right-left merit more attention partly due to the internationalization of the judiciary. In conclusion, I suggest that these comments should not diminish but rather increase the need for further research on the political and other ideological bias of the Norwegian Supreme Court – as of other parts of the domestic, regional and international judiciary. The appointment process and voting patterns of Supreme Court justices merit more public attention, e.g. as argued by present Chief Justice Schei – though not for the reasons claimed by Grendstad et al. |
Follesdal, Andreas: The Legitimacy Deficits of the Human Rights Judiciary: Elements and Implications of a Normative Theory. In: Theoretical Inquiries in Law, vol. 14, no. 2, pp. 339-360, 2013. (Type: Journal Article | Abstract | Links | Tags: Human Rights)@article{RN49341, The Article addresses some of the disagreement concerning the legitimacy of the international human rights judiciary. It lays out some aspects of a theory of legitimacy for the international human rights judiciary that seem relevant to addressing two challenges: First, it is difficult to justify the human rights judiciary by appeal to standard accounts of why states agree to subject themselves to treaties. What is the problem the international human rights judiciary is meant to help solve? Second, the human rights judiciary seems undemocratic and even antidemocratic when it overrules domestic, accountable legislatures. Such international judicial review is therefore sometimes thought to be normatively illegitimate, at least regarding democracies. |
Chavez, Leiry Cornejo; Follesdal, Andreas: Fragile Democracies, Strong Human Rights Courts? Comparing European and Inter-American Cases. In: Nordic Journal of Human Rights, vol. 31, no. 4, pp. 471-476, 2013. (Type: Journal Article | Abstract | Links | Tags: Democratic theory, European Court of Human Rights, Human Rights, Publications)@article{RN49685, Do regional Human Rights Courts strengthen democracy? If so, when and why does this occur: what are the scope conditions and intervening mechanisms that make such courts have positive effects? The articles in this special section address these questions as regards the European Court of Human Rights (ECtHR) and the Inter-American Court of Human Rights (IACtHR). Their similarities and differences allow several lessons to be drawn about the relationship between such courts and democracy….. |
Follesdal, Andreas: Will the Reform Treaty Combat the Union’s Legitimacy Crisis?. In: Merle, Jean-Christophe (Ed.): Die Legitimität von supranationalen Institutionen der EU, pp. 112-129, LIT-Verlag, Münster, 2012. (Type: Book Chapter | Abstract | Links | Tags: EU – European Union, Federalism, Publications)@inbook{RN48050, The Constitutional Treaty (CT) and the Reform Treaty (RT) does take several valuable steps to ensure that the European Union becomes more trustworthy and comes ‘closer to the people’ – though I register some ambivalence. Section 1 provides some fragments of the history of the European Union, to justify the diagnosis that it needs increased levels of trust and arrangements for trustworthiness among Europeans and their political leaders. Section 2 argues that the European Union has certain federal elements that require four peculiar forms of ‘balancing’. Section 4 discusses the increased need for trust among Europeans. Section 4 addresses the role of the Charter on Fundamental Rights as a trust building mechanism. Sections 5 to 7 address how the CT and the RT contribute or detract from each of these three forms of balancing. The conclusion is that certain elements of the CT and of the RT would help European institutions create and maintain their own support among European citizens and officials. |
Ulfstein, Geir; Føllesdal, Andreas: Den europeiske menneskerettighetsdomstolen og Høyesterett – uavhengighet og demokratisk kontroll. In: Engstad, Nils Asbjørn; Frøseth, Astrid Lærdal; Tønder, Bård (Ed.): Dommernes uavhengighet, pp. 443-461, Fagbokforlaget, Bergen, 2012. (Type: Book Chapter | Abstract | Links | Tags: )@inbook{RN49318, . I denne artikkelen drøfter vi prøvingen av norsk rett i forhold til Den europeiske menneskerettighetskonvensjonen (EMK) ved Den europeiske menneskerettighetsdomstolen (EMD) og av Høyesterett, både ut fra demokratiske legitimitet og mulige andre grunnlag for legitim myndighetsutøvelse. Vi peker til sist på hva denne internasjonaliseringen av retten kan og kanskje bør få å si for den allmenne oppfatningen av dommernes funksjoner i det norske samfunn og deres uavhengighet – og noen konsekvenser for utvelgelsen av dommere til Høyesterett og til internasjonale domstoler og medlemmer av menneskerettslige overvåkingsorganer. |
Follesdal, Andreas: Kata pengantar [Preface]. In: Rizki, Rudi M. (Ed.): Violations of Human Rights by transnational corporations and the effort to hold them accountable, pp. vii-ix, Penerbit PT Fikahati Aneska, Jakarta, 2012. (Type: Book Chapter | Tags: Human Rights)@inbook{RN49391, |
Follesdal, Andreas: Global Distributive Justice? State Boundaries as a Normative Problem. In: Global Constitutionalism, vol. 1, no. 2, pp. 261-277, 2012. (Type: Journal Article | Abstract | Links | Tags: Human Rights)@article{RN49225, Should state borders matter for claims of distributive justice? The article explores, only to reject, the best reasons for an “Anti-Cosmopolitan” position which grants some minimum international obligations, including social and economic human rights. At the same time this Anti-Cosmopolitanism rejects distinctly distributive principles of justice, familiar from discussions of justice among compatriots: There are no further limits on permissible global inequalities. “Anti-Cosmopolitans” do not deny that the tangled web of domestic and international institutions has a massive impact on individuals, their life plans and opportunities, albeit often indirectly and surreptitiously. What they deny is that claims to equality or limits to inequality should apply across state borders. The article explores what it is about states that can justify such a disjunct in the normative claims individuals have against each other. Several arguments about such alleged salient aspects of states and their constitutions are considered, but are found lacking. The main conclusion is to challenge the reasons Anti-Cosmopolitans offer against bringing distributive principles to the “Global Basic Structure.” |
Follesdal, Andreas: Europe’s Raison d’Être: Leadership, Democracy – or both? Reflections on G. de Burca and J. Weiler. In: Maastricht Journal of European and Comparative Law, vol. 19, no. 1, pp. 7-8, 2012. (Type: Journal Article | Abstract | Links | Tags: Democratic theory, Publications)@article{RN49272, What is at stake when the EU suffers from a legitimacy deficit, and what should be done about it? As always, Gráinne de Búrca and J H H Weiler identify and illuminate central issues of concern. de Búrca adroitly pinpoints a crux of the legitimacy debates in Europe: how to secure sufficient deference to EU decisions by citizens and national authorities. She is surely right to remind us that the EU’s legitimacy neither can nor should be based simply or primarily on democratic process legitimacy. But her pessimism may be premature, and her proposal of the EU as a global actor, whilst attractive, is not yet an obvious part of the solution. …successful resolution of this carefully selected set of problems will not reduce the need for democratic accountability, deliberation and contestation, but rather seems to require more of the same. |
Erman, Eva; Follesdal, Andreas: Multiple Citizenship: Normative Ideals and Institutional Challenges. In: Critical Review of International Social and Political Philosophy, vol. 15, no. 3, pp. 279-302, 2012. (Type: Journal Article | Abstract | Links | Tags: )@article{RN49123, Institutional suggestions for how to rethink democracy in response to changing state responsibilities and capabilities have been numerous and often mutually incompatible. This suggests that conceptual unclarity still reigns concerning how the normative ideal of democracy as collective self-determination, i.e. ‘rule by the people’, might best be brought to bear in a transnational and global context. The aim in this paper is twofold. First, it analyses some consequences of the tendency to smudge the distinction between democratic theory and moral theories of legitimacy and justice. Second, it develops a conceptual framework that distinguishes between necessary conditions, aspects and aims of democracy. On this basis it specifies three objectives of democracy, some of which may also hold for multilevel governance. It is argued that there are in principle at least three reasons to value democratic institutions: they are intrinsically justified to the extent that they distribute fair shares of political influence over decision-making; they are instrumentally justified to the extent that they secure several of our other best interests, one of which is our interest in non-domination; and finally, they are also instrumentally justified insofar as they secure the just distribution of other goods. The aim of this framework is not to develop a specific theory of multilevel governance but to point at important distinctions to be made and normative criteria to be specified. The intention is to take the debate forward by noting some of the issues that any satisfactory account must address. The framework lays out the grounds for analysing the institutional challenges facing legitimate multilevel governance through what is speculatively called ‘multiple citizenship’, understood in explorative terms, opening the door for the manifold roles that citizens could and ought to play in multilevel governance, not only as democratic agents, but also as agents of democracy and agents of justice. |
Nystuen, Gro; Follesdal, Andreas; Mestad, Ola: Human Rights, Corporate Complicity and Disinvestment. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, 2011. (Type: Book | Abstract | Links | Tags: Edited books, Human Rights, Publications, SRI – Socially responsible investing)@book{RN48520, How can businesses and their shareholders avoid moral and legal complicity in human rights violations? … In this volume legal scholars and political philosophers identify and address the intertwined issues of moral and legal complicity in human rights violations by companies and those who invest in them.. Contributors include, in addition to the editors; Simon Chesterman, Christopher Kutz, Urs Gasser, Helene Ingierd, Henrik Syse, Bruno Demeyere and Andrew Clapham |
Nystuen, Gro; Follesdal, Andreas; Mestad, Ola: Introduction. In: Nystuen, Gro; Follesdal, Andreas; Mestad, Ola (Ed.): Human Rights, Corporate Complicity and Disinvestment, pp. 1-15, Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, 2011. (Type: Book Chapter | Abstract | Links | Tags: Human Rights, Publications, SRI – Socially responsible investing)@inbook{RN48530, In the twenty-first century, questions of corporate conduct in relation to human rights have come to the forefront of public attention….Several institutional investors such as pension funds , especially responsible private funds and government funds have established policies and practices to handle issues of corporate involvement which they find unethical…. The discussions of the book lie at the intersection of three important current developments relating to normative frameworks: first, the corporate social responsibility (CSR ) discussion which addresses companies directly rather than the investors’ perspective; second, the ethical, or responsible, investment development; and third, discussions on norms for sovereign wealth funds that are investors of a special breed….It is against this normative background that this book analyses the relationships between investment, companies’ conduct and human rights…. Concepts of complicity in human rights violations are at the core of this book. They are discussed from several philosophical as well as several legal perspectives. The underlying discussion is how to establish norms for assessing corporate conduct and investors’ relationships to such conduct, and how to apply them?… |
Mansbridge, Jane J.; Bohman, James; Chambers, Simone; Estlund, David; Follesdal, Andreas; Fung, Archon; Lafont, Cristina; Bernard, Manin; Marti, José Luis: La place de l’intérêt particulier et le rôle du pouvoir dans la démocratie délibérative (The Place of Self-interest and the Role of Power in Deliberative Democracy). In: Raisons Politiques, vol. 42, pp. 47-82, 2011. (Type: Journal Article | Abstract | Links | Tags: Democratic theory, Publications)@article{RN48982, Translation of 2010 article in Journal of Political Philosophy. Cet article avance, à contre-courant de toutes les théories délibératives existantes, que les intérêts particuliers doivent être pris en compte dans la délibération démocratique. Deux conditions sont cependant nécessaires afin que l’inclusion des intérêts particuliers dans la délibération apparaisse légitime : l’idéal-régulateur d’absence de pouvoir coercitif et l’encadrement des intérêts particuliers par des principes de justice. Ceci conduit à qualifier de ‘délibératives’ des formes de négociation mettant en jeu des intérêts contradictoires, telles que la négociation intégrative et la négociation ‘parfaitement coopérative’. L’article se conclut en défendant la complémentarité de la délibération et de mécanismes démocratiques agrégatifs et non-délibératifs. Based on ‘The Place of Self-interest and the Role of Power in Deliberative Democracy’ in Journal of Political Philosophy 2010 |
Publications
Add international courts to The Idea of Human Rights and stir … on Beitz’ The Idea of Human Rights after 10 years. In: Álvarez, David; Rosas, João Cardoso (Ed.): The Idea of Human Rights Revisited: Charles Beitz and the Political Turn in the Philosophy of Human Rights, Routledge, 2023. | :
In defense of deference: International human rights as standards of review. In: Journal of Social Philosophy, vol. 54, no. 4, pp. 526-547, 2023. | :
A just yet unequal European Union: A defense of moderate economic inequality. In: Review of Social Economy, vol. 81, no. 1, pp. 8-36, 2023. | :
Situated and Universal: Special Issue in Honor of Geir Ulfstein. Nordic Journal of International Law, 2022. | :
Introduction to Special Issue in Honor of Geir Ulfstein. In: Nordic Journal of International Law, vol. 91, no. 4, pp. 541-543, 2022. | :
The Significance of State Consent for the Legitimate Authority of Customary International Law. In: Merkouris, Panos; Kammerhofer, Jörg; Arajärvi, Noora (Ed.): The Theory, Practice and Interpretation of Customary International Law, pp. 105-136, Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, 2022. | :
Federalism. In: Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy, no. 2022, 2022. | :
Add international courts to The Idea of Human Rights and stir … on Beitz’ The Idea of Human Rights after 10 years. In: Critical Review of International Social and Political Philosophy, vol. 25, no. 1, pp. 66-86, 2022. | :
Gender imbalance on the international bench: is normative legitimacy at stake?. In: Journal of Social Philosophy, vol. 52, no. 4, pp. 430-435, 2021. | :
Mediating unity and diversity through Federalism in Ethiopia. Special Issue. International Journal on Minority and Group Rights, 2021. | :
Introducing David Lefkowitz’s Philosophy and International Law. In: EJIL:Talk – Blog of the European Journal of International Law, 2021. | :
Stability and trust in federations with ethnic territories and a secession clause – challenges and opportunities for Ethiopia. In: International Journal on Minority and Group Rights, 2021. | :
Pure Public Goods and Beyond: How Legitimate International Courts Can Help Secure Global Public Goods Worth Having. In: Zyberi, Gentian (Ed.): Protecting Community Interests through International Law, pp. 59-98, Intersentia, Cambridge, 2021. | :
International human rights courts and the (international) rule of law: Part of the solution, part of the problem, or both?. In: Global Constitutionalism, vol. 10, no. 1, pp. 118-138, 2021. | :
How many women judges are enough on international courts?. In: Journal of Social Philosophy, vol. 52, no. 4, pp. 436-458, 2021. | :
The Relationship Between the European Convention on Human Rights and Wider International Law – Special Issue. International Journal on Human Rights, 2020. | :
The European Convention on Human Rights and other parts of international law. In: International Journal on Human Rights, vol. 24, no. 7, pp. 913-16, 2020. | :
Survey Article: The Legitimacy of International Courts. In: Journal of Political Philosophy, vol. 28, no. 4, pp. 475-499, 2020. | :
Religion and the State – the European Court of Human Rights and the ‘Lautsi’ case of the European Court of Human Rights about crucifixes in Italian class rooms. In: Ehlers, Dirk; Glaser, Henning (Ed.): State and Religion: Between Conflict and Cooperation, pp. 315 – 330, Nomos, Baden Baden, 2020. | :
Challenges to the legitimacy of the European Union: When and how are European courts also part of the solution?. In: xx, 2019. | :
Legitimacy criticisms of international courts: Not only Fuzzy Rhetoric?. In: Sadurski, Wojciech; Sevel, Michael; Walton, Kevin (Ed.): Legitimacy: The State and Beyond, pp. 223-237, Oxford University Press, Oxford, 2019. | :
The European Research Council @ 10: Whither hopes and fears?. In: European Political Science, vol. 18, no. 2, pp. 237-247, 2019. | :
The European Research Council @ 10: What has it done to us?. In: European Political Science, vol. 18, no. 2, pp. 234-36, 2019. | :
A better Signpost, not a better walking Stick: How to evaluate the European Consensus doctrine. In: Kapotas, Panos; Tzevelokos, Vassilis (Ed.): Building Consensus on European Consensus: Judicial Interpretation of Human Rights in Europe and Beyond, pp. 189-209, Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, 2019. | :
The Performance of International Courts and Tribunals. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, 2018, ((i) the IC’s output: its judgments and interpretations; (ii) its outcome in the sense of states’ compliance with particular judgments; and (iii) the ultimate broader impact of such compliance on the ground.). | :
A framework for evaluating the performance of international courts and tribunals. In: Squatrito, Theresa; Young, Oran; Follesdal, Andreas; Ulfstein, Geir (Ed.): The Performance of International Courts and Tribunals, pp. 3-35, Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, 2018. | :
Politikk og menneskerettigheter. Aschehoug, Oslo, 2018. | :
The legitimacy of international courts. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, 2018. | :
Legitimacy and international courts – a framework. In: Grossman, Nienke; Cohen, Harlan; Follesdal, Andreas; Ulfstein, Geir (Ed.): The legitimacy of international courts, pp. 1-40, Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, 2018. | :
The Judicialization of International Law – A Mixed Blessing?. Oxford University Press, Oxford, 2018. | :
International Courts and Tribunals: Rise and Reactions. In: Follesdal, Andreas; Ulfstein, Geir (Ed.): The Judicialization of International Law – A Mixed Blessing?, pp. 1-8, Oxford University Press, Oxford, 2018. | :
Power or Authority; Actions or Beliefs. In: Alter, Karen; Helfer, Laurence; Madsen, Mikael Rask (Ed.): International Court Authority, pp. 412-421, Oxford University Press, New York, 2018. | :
More than meets the eye – and less: On The Internationalists. In: Global Constitutionalism, vol. 7, no. 3, pp. 330-341, 2018. | :
The Legitimate Authority of International Courts and its Limits: A challenge to Raz’ Service Conception?. In: Capps, Patrick; Olsen, Henrik Palmer (Ed.): Legal authority beyond the state, pp. 188-205, Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, 2018. | :
Constitutionalization, not democratization: how to assess the legitimacy of international courts. In: Grossman, Nienke; Cohen, Harlan; Follesdal, Andreas; Ulfstein, Geir (Ed.): The legitimacy of international courts, pp. 307-337, Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, 2018. | :
Appreciating the Margin of Appreciation. In: Etinson, Adam (Ed.): Human Rights: Moral or Political?, pp. 269-294, Oxford University Press, Oxford, 2018. | :
Humanistisk forskning for et samfunn i forandring. In: Nytt Norsk Tidsskrift, vol. 34, no. 1, pp. 51-57, 2017, ISSN: 0800-336x. | :
The International Human Rights Judiciary and National Parliaments: Europe and Beyond. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, 2017. | :
Menneskerettighetene og Norge: Rettsutvikling, rettsliggjøring og demokrati. Universitetsforlaget, Oslo, 2017. | :
De internasjonale menneskerettighetene og Norge: Spenninger og samspill. In: Føllesdal, Andreas; Ruud, Morten; Ulfstein, Geir (Ed.): Menneskerettighetene og Norge: Rettsutvikling, rettsliggjøring og demokrati, pp. 13-32, Universitetsforlaget, Oslo, 2017. | :
Tracking justice democratically. In: Social Epistemology, vol. 31, no. 3, pp. 324-339, 2017. | :
Theories of Human Rights: Political or Orthodox – why it matters. In: Maliks, Reidar; Karlsson, Johan Schaffer (Ed.): Moral and Political Conceptions of Human Rights: Implications for Theory and Practice, pp. 77-96, Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, 2017. | :
Law making by law breaking? A theory of parliamentary civil disobedience against international human rights courts. In: Saul, Matthew; Follesdal, Andreas; Ulfstein, Geir (Ed.): The International Human Rights Judiciary and National Parliaments: Europe and Beyond, pp. 329-352, Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, 2017. | :
Independent yet Accountable: Stress Test Lessons for the European Court of Human Rights. In: Maastricht Journal of European and Comparative Law, vol. 24, no. 4, pp. 484-510, 2017. | :
Getting to Justice? On Albert Weale: Democratic Justice. In: Critical Review of International Social and Political Philosophy, vol. 20, no. 2, pp. 231-242, 2017. | :
Exporting the Margin of Appreciation: Lessons for the Inter-American Court of Human Rights?. In: International journal of constitutional law, vol. 15, no. 2, pp. 359-371, 2017. | :
Democracy and regional human rights courts: Enemies, allies, or both? Symposium. International Journal of Constitutional Law, 2017. | :
Democracy and regional human rights courts. In: International Journal of Constitutional Law, vol. 15, no. 2, pp. 358, 2017. | :
The margin of appreciation in Europe and beyond – Special Issue. The International Journal of Human Rights, 2016. | :
The European Court of Human Rights and national courts: a constitutional relationship?. In: Arnardóttir, Oddný Mjöll; Buyse, Antoine (Ed.): Shifting Centres of Gravity in Human Rights Protection, pp. 46-56, Routledge, London, 2016. | :
The margin of appreciation in Europe and beyond. In: The International Journal of Human Rights, vol. 20, no. 8, pp. 1055-1057, 2016. | :
Subsidiarity to the Rescue for the European Courts? Resolving tensions between the Margin of Appreciation and Human Rights Protection. In: Heidemann, Dietmar; Stoppenbrink, Katja (Ed.): Join, or Die – Philosophical Foundations of Federalism, pp. 251-272, de Gruyter, Berlin, 2016. | :
Subsidiarity and international human rights courts: respecting self-governance and protecting human rights – or neither?. In: Law and Contemporary Problems, vol. 79, no. 2, pp. 147-163, 2016. | :
Squaring the Circle at the Battle at Brighton: Is the War between protecting human rights or respecting sovereignty over, or has it just begun?. In: Arnardóttir, Oddný Mjöll; Buyse, Antoine (Ed.): Shifting Centres of Gravity in Human Rights Protection: Rethinking Relations between the ECHR, EU, and National Legal Orders, pp. 189-204, Routledge, London, 2016. | :
Implications of contested multilateralism for global constitutionalism. In: Global Constitutionalism, vol. 5, no. 3, pp. 297-308, 2016. | :
Building democracy at the bar: The European Court of Human Rights as an agent of transitional cosmopolitanism. In: Transnational Legal Theory, no. special issue, ed. Claudio Corradetti, pp. 95-113, 2016. | :
The Principle of Subsidiarity as a constitutional principle in the EU and Canada. In: Les Ateliers de l’Éthique/The Ethics Forum, vol. 10, no. 2, pp. 89-206, 2015. | :
Social Primary Goods. In: Mandle, Jon; Reidy, David (Ed.): The Cambridge Rawls Lexicon, pp. 643-647, Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, 2015. | :
Machiavelli at 500: From Cynic to Vigilant Supporter of International Law. In: Ratio Juris, vol. 28, no. 2, pp. 242-51, 2015. | :
International Human Rights Courts: Beyond a State of Nature – Foreword. In: Ajevski, Marjan (Ed.): Fragmentation in International Human Rights Law: Beyond Conflicts of Laws, pp. xi-xviii, Routledge, London, 2015. | :
Curb, Channel and Coordinate: The Constitutionalisation of International Courts and Tribunals. In: Baere, Geert De; Wouters, Jan (Ed.): The Contribution of International and Supranational Courts to the Rule of Law, pp. 355-369, Elgar Publishing, Cheltenham, 2015. | :
Fragmentation in International Human Rights Law: Beyond Conflicts of Laws. Routledge, London, 2015. | :
Subsidiarity and the global order. In: Zimmermann, Augusto; Evans, Michelle (Ed.): Global Perspectives on Subsidiarity, pp. 207-220, Springer, Dordrecht, 2014. | :
Engagement, divestment, or both? Conflicts and interactions: The case of the Norwegian Pension Fund. In: Bohoslavsky, Juan Pablo; Cernic, Jernej Letnar (Ed.): Sovereign Financing, pp. 323-336, Hart, Oxford, 2014. | :
The European Court of Human Rights and the Norwegian Supreme Court – Independence and Democratic Control. In: Engstad, Nils Asbjørn; Frøseth, Astrid Lærdal; Tønder, Bård (Ed.): The Independence of Judges, pp. 247-260, Eleven, 2014. | :
Kantian theory and human rights. In: Follesdal, Andreas; Maliks, Reidar (Ed.): Kantian theory and human rights, pp. 1-7, Routledge, 2014. | :
Hvis det norske forbudet mot dobbelt statsborgerskap er løsningen, hva er da problemet?. In: Langeland, Nils Rune (Ed.): Politisk kompetanse: grunnlovas borgar 1814-2014, pp. 78-87, Pax, Oslo, 2014. | :
Del av problemet, og del av løsningen: Den europeiske menneskerettighetsdomstolen og demokratisk selvstyre. In: Baldersheim, Harald; Østerud, Øyvind (Ed.): Det norske demokratiet i det 21. århundre, pp. 80-91, Fagbokforlaget, Oslo, 2014. | :
Kantian theory and human rights. Routledge, 2014. | :
Subsidiarity and the global order. In: Zimmermann, Augusto; Evans, Michelle (Ed.): Global Perspectives on Subsidiarity, pp. 207-220, Springer, Dordrecht, 2014. | :
Okin, Susan. In: Gibbons, Michael; Coole, Diana; Ellis, Elisabeth (Ed.): Encyclopedia of Political Thought, Wiley-Blackwell, 2014, ISBN: 978-1-4051-9129-6. | :
Legitimacy Challenges and what to do about them – Accountability and authority of the European Court of Human Rights. In: Proceedings of Conference on the Long-term future of the European Court of Human Rights, pp. 78-85, 2014. | :
Kant, Human Rights, and Courts. In: Follesdal, Andreas; Maliks, Reidar (Ed.): Kantian theory and human rights, pp. 193-202, Routledge, 2014. | :
John Rawls’ Theory of Justice as Fairness. In: Fløistad, Guttorm (Ed.): Philosophy of Justice, pp. 311-328, Springer, Dordrecht, 2014. | :
Guiding and guarding international judges. In: New York University School of Law Journal of International Law and Politics, vol. 46, no. 3, pp. 793-808, 2014. | :
Global Citizenship. In: Sterri, Aksel Braanen (Ed.): Global Citizen – Challenges and Responsibility in an Interconnected World, pp. 71-82, Sense, Rotterdam, 2014. | :
Federalism and Human Rights in Nepal’s Constitutional Design: Challenges for the Judiciary. In: Ehlers, Dirk; Glaser, Hennig; Prokati, Kittisak (Ed.): Constitutionalism and good governance: Western and Eastern perspectives, vol. 1, pp. 193-203, Nomos, Baden Baden, 2014. | :
Democratic standards in an asymmetric Union. In: Cramme, Olaf; Hobolt, Sara B. (Ed.): Democratic Politics in a European Union under Stress, pp. 199 -216, Oxford University Press, Oxford, 2014. | :
Democracy, identity, and European public spheres. In: Risse, Thomas (Ed.): European Public Spheres: Politics is Back, pp. 247-262, Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, 2014. | :
Competing Conceptions of Subsidiarity. In: Fleming, James E.; Levy, Jacob T. (Ed.): Nomos LV: Federalism and Subsidiarity, pp. 214-230, New York University Press, New York, 2014. | :
A common European identity for European citizenship?. In: German Law Journal, vol. 15, no. 5, pp. 765-775, 2014, (Nivå 1). | :
International human rights and the challenge of legitimacy. In: Follesdal, Andreas; Schaffer, Johan; Ulfstein, Geir (Ed.): The Legitimacy of International Human Rights Regimes, pp. 1-30, Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, 2013. | :
The Legitimacy of International Human Rights Regimes: Legal, Political and Philosophical Perspectives. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, 2013. | :
Introduction. In: Follesdal, Andreas; Peters, Birgit; Ulfstein, Geir (Ed.): Constituting Europe: The European Court of Human Rights in a National, European and Global Context, pp. 1-24, Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, 2013. | :
Constituting Europe: The European Court of Human Rights in a national, European and global context. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, 2013. | :
Conclusions. In: Follesdal, Andreas; Peters, Birgit; Ulfstein, Geir (Ed.): Constituting Europe: The European Court of Human Rights in a National, European and Global Context, pp. 389-402, Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, 2013. | :
Subsidiarity as a Constitutional Principle in International Law. In: Global Constitutionalism, vol. 2, no. 1, pp. 37-62, 2013. | :
Much ado about Nothing? International Judicial Review of Human Rights in Well Functioning Democracies. In: Follesdal, Andreas; Schaffer, Johan; Ulfstein, Geir (Ed.): The Legitimacy of International Human Rights Regimes, pp. 272-299, Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, 2013. | :
Much Ado about Nothing? Claims about political appointment to the Norwegian Supreme Court – and what to do – and not to do – about it. In: Tidsskrift for rettsvitenskap, no. 3, pp. 365-371, 2013, (Grendstad). | :
The Legitimacy Deficits of the Human Rights Judiciary: Elements and Implications of a Normative Theory. In: Theoretical Inquiries in Law, vol. 14, no. 2, pp. 339-360, 2013. | :
Fragile Democracies, Strong Human Rights Courts? Comparing European and Inter-American Cases. In: Nordic Journal of Human Rights, vol. 31, no. 4, pp. 471-476, 2013. | :
Will the Reform Treaty Combat the Union’s Legitimacy Crisis?. In: Merle, Jean-Christophe (Ed.): Die Legitimität von supranationalen Institutionen der EU, pp. 112-129, LIT-Verlag, Münster, 2012. | :
Den europeiske menneskerettighetsdomstolen og Høyesterett – uavhengighet og demokratisk kontroll. In: Engstad, Nils Asbjørn; Frøseth, Astrid Lærdal; Tønder, Bård (Ed.): Dommernes uavhengighet, pp. 443-461, Fagbokforlaget, Bergen, 2012. | :
Kata pengantar [Preface]. In: Rizki, Rudi M. (Ed.): Violations of Human Rights by transnational corporations and the effort to hold them accountable, pp. vii-ix, Penerbit PT Fikahati Aneska, Jakarta, 2012. | :
Global Distributive Justice? State Boundaries as a Normative Problem. In: Global Constitutionalism, vol. 1, no. 2, pp. 261-277, 2012. | :
Europe’s Raison d’Être: Leadership, Democracy – or both? Reflections on G. de Burca and J. Weiler. In: Maastricht Journal of European and Comparative Law, vol. 19, no. 1, pp. 7-8, 2012. | :
Multiple Citizenship: Normative Ideals and Institutional Challenges. In: Critical Review of International Social and Political Philosophy, vol. 15, no. 3, pp. 279-302, 2012. | :
Human Rights, Corporate Complicity and Disinvestment. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, 2011. | :
Introduction. In: Nystuen, Gro; Follesdal, Andreas; Mestad, Ola (Ed.): Human Rights, Corporate Complicity and Disinvestment, pp. 1-15, Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, 2011. | :
La place de l’intérêt particulier et le rôle du pouvoir dans la démocratie délibérative (The Place of Self-interest and the Role of Power in Deliberative Democracy). In: Raisons Politiques, vol. 42, pp. 47-82, 2011. | :